Bob his bib refs

last update on 04 September 2025

[1] Kjartan Koch Mikalsen. The irrelevance of history. Ratio Juris, 33(3), 2020.
[2] Peter Laslett. Philosophy, Politics and Society. Basil Blackwell, 1975.
[3] Bernard Williams. In the beginning was the deed. Princeton University Press, 2008.
[4] Samuel Freeman. Rawls. Routledge, 2007.
[5] John Rawls and Samuel Freeman. Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy. Harvard University Press, 2021.
This last book by the late John Rawls, derived from written lectures and notes for his long-running course on modern political philosophy, offers readers an account of the liberal political tradition from a scholar viewed by many as the greatest contemporary exponent of the philosophy behind that tradition. Rawls's goal in the lectures was, he wrote, "to identify the more central features of liberalism as expressing a political conception of justice when liberalism is viewed from within the tradition of democratic constitutionalism." He does this by looking at several strands that make up the liberal and democratic constitutional traditions, and at the historical figures who best represent these strands-among them the contractarians Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau; the utilitarians Hume, Sidgwick, and J. S. Mill; and Marx regarded as a critic of liberalism. Rawls's lectures on Bishop Joseph Butler also are included in an appendix. Constantly revised and refined over three decades, Rawls's lectures on these figures reflect his developing and changing views on the history of liberalism and democracy-as well as how he saw his own work in relation to those traditions. With its clear and careful analyses of the doctrine of the social contract, utilitarianism, and socialism-and of their most influential proponents-this volume has a critical place in the traditions it expounds. Marked by Rawls's characteristic patience and curiosity, and scrupulously edited by his student and teaching assistant, Samuel Freeman, these lectures are a fitting final addition to his oeuvre, and to the history of political philosophy as well.
[6] John Rawls. Political Liberalism : Expanded Edition. Columbia University Press, 2011.
This book continues and revises the ideas of justice as fairness that John Rawls presented in A Theory of Justice but changes its philosophical interpretation in a fundamental way. That previous work assumed what Rawls calls a "well-ordered society," one that is stable and relatively homogenous in its basic moral beliefs and in which there is broad agreement about what constitutes the good life. Yet in modern democratic society a plurality of incompatible and irreconcilable doctrines-religious, philosophical, and moral-cuxist within the framework of democratic institutions. Recognizing this as a permanent condition of democracy, Rawls asks how a stable and just society of free and equal citizens can live in concord when divided by reasonable but incompatible doctrines' This edition includes the essay "The Idea of Public Reason Revisited," which outlines Rawls' plans to revise Political Liberalism, which were cut short by his death. "An extraordinary well-reasoned commentary on A Theory of Justice ... a decisive turn towards political philosophy."--Times Literary Supplement.
[7] Jonathan Floyd and Marc Stears, editors. Political Philosophy versus History? Cambridge University Press, 2012.
[8] M. Thaler. Political judgment beyond paralysis and heroism. European Journal of Political Theory, 10(2), 2011.
[9] Jacques Derrida. Margins of Philosophy. The Harvester Press, 1 edition, 1982.
[10] Jacques Derrida. Of Grammatology. Johns Hopkins University Press, 2016.
[11] Drucilla Cornell, Michel Rosenfeld, David Carlson, and Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law. Deconstruction and the possibility of justice. Routledge, New York, 1992.
Most of these papers were presented at a symposium held at the Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law on October 1-2, 1989.
Keywords: Derrida Jacques 1930- ; Derrida Jacques ; Law -- Interpretation and construction ; Law -- Political aspects ; Law ; Postmodernism ; Deconstruction ; Droit et politique ; Dekonstruktion ; Rechtsphilosophie ; Kongress ; Gerechtigkeit ; Justice ; Droit -- Interprétation ; Jurisprudence ; 86.04 philosophy of law
[12] Clare Connors. Force from Nietzsche to Derrida. Routledge, Oxford, 1 edition, 2010.
'What is the pervasive character of the world? The answer is force.' But, as Heidegger asks next: ' What is force?' Connors sets out to answer this question, tracing --- through a series of close readings --- a genealogy of the idea of force through the writings of Nietzsche, Heidegger, Foucault and Derrida. These thinkers try to pin down what force is, but know too that it is something which cannot be neutrally described, and cannot be discussed without loss or bias. Their vigorously literary writings must therefore be read as much for the stylistic and rhetorical ways in which they render force's powerful elusiveness as for the content of their arguments. And it is perhaps literature, rather than philosophy, which best engages with force. Certainly these philosophical positions are foreshadowed in remarkable detail by Shakespeare's Henry V--- a play shot through with forces, imaginary, military, rhetorical and bodily.
Keywords: 20th Century ; Force and energy ; Power (Philosophy) ; Power (Philosophy) in literature ; Violence - Social aspects
[13] Michel Foucault. The subject and power. Critical inquiry, 8(4), 1982.
Keywords: Commercial production ; Conceptualization ; Denial ; Individualization ; Mode of action ; Political power ; Rationality ; Rationalization ; Reason ; Subjectivity
[14] Michel Foucault, Michel Senellart, François Ewald, Alessandro Fontana, Arnold Ira Davidson, Graham Burchell, François Ewald, Alessandro Fontana, and Michel Senellart. On the government of the living : lectures at the Collège de France, 1979-1980. Michel Foucault, Lectures at the Collège de France. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke, 1 edition, 2014.
01 02 In these lectures delivered in 1980, Michel Foucault gives an important new inflection to his history of 'regimes of truth.' Following on from the themes of knowledge-power and governmentality, he turns his attention here to the ethical domain of practices of techniques of the self. Why and how, he asks, does the exercise of power as government demand not only acts of obedience and submission, but 'truth acts' in which individuals subject to relations of power are also required to be subjects in procedures of truth-telling? How and why are subjects required not just to tell the truth, but to tell the truth about themselves? These questions lead to a re-reading of Sophocles' Oedipus the King and, through an examination of the texts of Tertullian, Cassian and others, to an analysis of the 'truth acts' in early Christian practices of baptism, penance, and spiritual direction in which believers are called upon to manifest the truth of themselves as subjects always danger of falling into sin. In the public expression of the subject's condition as a sinner, in the rituals of repentance and penance, and in the detailed verbalization of thoughts in the examination of conscience, we see the organization of a pastoral system focused upon confession. 13 02 Michel Foucault, acknowledged as the pre-eminent philosopher of France in the 1970s and 1980s, continues to have enormous impact throughout the world in many disciplines. Arnold I. Davidson, Series Editor, is the Robert O. Anderson Distinguished Service Professor at the University of Chicago, USA, and Professor of the Philosophy of Cultures at the Università Ca'Foscari, Venice. He is co-editor of the volume Michel Foucault: Philosophie. Graham Burchell is a translator. As well as translating Foucault's lectures at the Collège de France he has written essays on Foucault's work and was an editor of and contributor to the influential volume The Foucault Effect. Studies in Governmentality. 02 02 With these lectures Foucault inaugurates his investigations of truth-telling in the ethical domain of practices of techniques of the self. How and why, he asks, does the government of men require those subject to power to be subjects who must tell the truth about themselves? 08 02 "[Foucault] must be reckoned with." -- The New York Times Book Review "Ideas spark off nearly every page of this book, as Foucault manages to reinvigorate questions of power and violence that might have seemed well-worn. The words may have been spoken in 1976, but they seem as alive and relevant as if they had been written yesterday." -- Bookforum "Foucault is quite central to our sense of where we are..." -- The Nation "[Foucault] has an alert and sensitive mind that can ignore the familiar surfaces of established intellectual coded and ask new questions...[He] gives dramatic quality to the movement of culture." -- The New York Review of Books "These lectures offer important insights into the evolution of the primary focus of Foucault's later work -- the relationship between power and knowledge." - Library Journal 04 02 Foreword: François Ewald and Alessandro Fontana Translator's Note Abbreviations 1. 9 January 1980 2. 16 January 1980 3. 23 January 1980 4. 30 January 1980 5. 6 February 1980 6. 13 February 1980 7. 20 February 1980 8. 27 February 1980 9. 5 March 1980 10. 12 March 1980 11. 19 March 1980 12. 16 March 1980 Course Summary Course Context Index of Greek Terms Index of Notions Index of Names
Keywords: General Philosophy and Philosophers ; Law ; Law -- Philosophy ; Modern Philosophy ; Palgrave Religion & Philosophy Collection ; PHILOSOPHY ; Political ; Political and Social Philosophy ; Political aspects ; Political Philosophy ; Political science ; Political science -- Philosophy ; Social Philosophy ; Truth ; Truth -- Political aspects ; Truth -- Religious aspects ; Truth in literature ; Western philosophy from c 1900
[15] Michel Foucault. What is Critique?, volume 7 of Philosophical traditions, pages 382--398. University of California Press, Berkeley, 1 edition, 1996.
This collection contains the first English translations of a group of important eighteenth-century German essays that address the question, "What is Enlightenment?" The book also includes newly translated and newly written interpretive essays by leading historians and philosophers, which examine the origins of eighteenth-century debate on Enlightenment and explore its significance for the present. In recent years, critics from across the political and philosophical spectrum have condemned the Enlightenment for its complicity with any number of present-day social and cultural maladies. It has rarely been noticed, however, that at the end of the Enlightenment, German thinkers had already begun a scrutiny of their age so wide-ranging that there are few subsequent criticisms that had not been considered by the close of the eighteenth century. Among the concerns these essays address are the importance of freedom of expression, the relationship between faith and reason, and the responsibility of the Enlightenment for revolutions. Included are translations of works by such well-known figures as Immanuel Kant, Moses Mendelssohn, Johann Gottlieb Fichte, and Johann Georg Hamann, as well as essays by thinkers whose work is virtually unknown to American readers. These eighteenth-century texts are set against interpretive essays by such major twentieth-century figures as Max Horkheimer, Jürgen Habermas, and Michel Foucault.
Keywords: Enlightenment ; Cultural life ; Freedom of thought ; Intellectual life ; Intellectuals ; Philosophical thought ; Philosophy ; Public sphere ; Reason ; Texts
[16] Michel Foucault and Paul. Rabinow. The Foucault reader. Penguin Books, London [etc, repr. edition, 1991.
Keywords: Foucault Michel 1926-1984 ; Philosophy ; 08.20 history of western philosophy: general
[17] Raymond Geuss. Philosophy and real politics. Princeton University Press, Princeton, course book edition, 2008.
Many contemporary political thinkers are gripped by the belief that their task is to develop an ideal theory of rights or justice for guiding and judging political actions. But in Philosophy and Real Politics, Raymond Geuss argues that philosophers should first try to understand why real political actors behave as they actually do. Far from being applied ethics, politics is a skill that allows people to survive and pursue their goals. To understand politics is to understand the powers, motives, and concepts that people have and that shape how they deal with the problems they face in their particular historical situations. Philosophy and Real Politics both outlines a historically oriented, realistic political philosophy and criticizes liberal political philosophies based on abstract conceptions of rights and justice. The book is a trenchant critique of established ways of thought and a provocative call for change.
Keywords: Philosophy ; PHILOSOPHY / Political ; Conceptualization ; Ethics & Moral Philosophy ; Judgement ; Justice ; Liberalism ; Political ; Political philosophy ; Political action ; Political behaviour ; Political science ; Political science -- Philosophy ; Realism ; Rights
[18] Raymond Geuss. Outside ethics. Princeton University Press, Princeton, N.J, 2005.
Outside Ethics brings together some of the most important and provocative works by one of the most creative philosophers writing today. Seeking to expand the scope of contemporary moral and political philosophy, Raymond Geuss here presents essays bound by a shared skepticism about a particular way of thinking about what is important in human life--a way of thinking that, in his view, is characteristic of contemporary Western societies and isolates three broad categories of things as important: subjective individual preferences, knowledge, and restrictions on actions that affect other people (restrictions often construed as ahistorical laws). He sets these categories in a wider context and explores various human phenomena--including poetry, art, religion, and certain kinds of history and social criticism--that do not fit easily into these categories. As its title suggests, this book seeks a place outside conventional ethics. Following a brief introduction, Geuss sets out his main concerns with a focus on ethics and politics. He then expands these themes by discussing freedom, virtue, the good life, and happiness. Next he examines Theodor Adorno's views on the relation between suffering and knowledge, the nature of religion, and the role of history in giving us critical distances from existing identities. From here he moves to aesthetic concerns. The volume closes by looking at what it is for a human life to have "gaps"--to be incomplete, radically unsatisfactory, or a failure.
Keywords: Ethics ; Liberalism ; Philosophy
[19] Reinhart. Koselleck. Futures past. Columbia University Press, New York, 2004.
With a new, interpretive introduction by the translator, this revised edition of Koselleck's most acclaimed work is once again available in English. Koselleck explores the concept of historical time by posing the question: What kind of experience is opened up by the emergence of modernity? Koselleck explores the concept of historical time by posing the question: what kind of experience is opened up by the emergence of modernity?
Keywords: History -- Philosophy ; History -- Periodization ; History
QHistory -- Terminology ; Historiography
[20] Paul Sagar. Adam Smith Reconsidered. Princeton University Press, 2022.
Keywords: Rousseau; Smith; Hume; Mandeville
[21] Allen W. Wood. Idea for a universal history with a cosmopolitan aim (1784). In Anthropology, History, and Education, pages 107--120. Cambridge University Press, United States, 2007.
TRANSLATOR'S INTRODUCTIONThis essay appears to have been occasioned by a passing remark made by Kant's colleague and follower Johann Schultz in a 1784 article in the Gotha Learned Papers (see Note 1 below). In order to make good on Schultz's remark, Kant wrote this article, which appeared in the Berli- nische Monatsschrift late in the same year.This is the first, and despite its brevity the most fully worked out, statement of his philosophy of history. Theideareferred to in the title is a theoretical idea, that is, an a priori conception of a theoretical program to maximize the comprehensibility of human history. It anticipates much of the theory of the use of natural teleology in the theoretical understanding of nature that Kant was to develop over five years later in the Critique of the Power of Judgment. But this theoretical idea also stands in a close and complex relationship to Kant's moral and political philosophy, and to his conception of practical faith in divine providence. Especially prominent in it is the first statement of Kant's famous conception of a federation of states united to secure perpetual peace between nations.The Idea for a Universal History also contained several propositions that were soon to be disputed by J. G. Herder in his Ideas for the Philosophy of the History of Humanity, leading to Kant's reply in his reviews of that work (1785) and in the Conjectural Beginning of Human History (1786).
Keywords: PHILOSOPHY ; Philosophy: epistemology & theory of knowledge ; Western philosophy
[22] Bernard Williams and Geoffrey Hawthorn. Realism and moralism in political theory. In In the Beginning Was the Deed, pages 1--. Princeton University Press, stu - student edition edition, 2009.
I start with two rough models of political theory (or philosophy: the distinction is not important here) with respect to the relation of morality to political practice. One is anenactmentmodel. The model is that political theory formulates principles, concepts, ideals, and values; and politics (so far as it does what the theory wants) seeks to express these in political action, through persuasion, the use of power, and so forth. This is not necessarily (although it is usually) a distinction between persons. Moreover, there is an intermediate activity which can be shared by both parties: this shapes particular conceptions
Keywords: Political power ; Applied philosophy ; Axiology ; Behavioral sciences ; Coercion ; Cognitive psychology ; Critical theory ; Emotion ; Emotional states ; Ethics ; Fear ; Human aggression ; Human behavior ; Liberalism ; Metanarratives ; Moralism ; Morality ; Normative ethics ; Normativity ; Philosophy ; Political attitudes ; Political ethics ; Political ideologies ; Political philosophy ; Political science ; Political sociology ; Politics ; Psychology ; Social behavior ; Social criticism ; Social philosophy
[23] John Rawls. A theory of justice. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1971.
John Rawls aims to express an essential part of the common core of the democratic tradition---justice as fairness---and to provide an alternative to utilitarianism, which had dominated the Anglo-Saxon tradition of political thought since the nineteenth century. Rawls substitutes the ideal of the social contract as a more satisfactory account of the basic rights and liberties of citizens as free and equal persons. “Each person,” writes Rawls, “possesses an inviolability founded on justice that even the welfare of society as a whole cannot override.” Advancing the ideas of Rousseau, Kant, Emerson, and Lincoln, Rawls's theory is as powerful today as it was when first published. Though the revised edition of A Theory of Justice, published in 1999, is the definitive statement of Rawls's view, much of the extensive literature on his theory refers to the original. This first edition is available for scholars and serious students of Rawls's work.
Keywords: Justice ; Social justice ; Philosophy
[24] Quentin Skinner and David Miller. A third concept of liberty. In Liberty Reader, pages 243--254. Routledge, United Kingdom, 1 edition, 2006.
The Act of March 1649 abolishing the office of king confirmed that monarchy is 'dangerous to the liberty, safety, and public interest of the people', and added that in England the effect of the prerogative has been 'to oppress and impoverish and enslave the subject'. Having raised the question, however, Isaiah Berlin confidently answers that no such third concept of liberty can be coherently entertained. To speak of dependence as lack of liberty, he writes, would be to confound freedom with other concepts in a manner at once misleading and confused. Stating his grounds for this conclusion, Berlin goes on to enunciate his most general claim about the concept of liberty. When he discusses negative liberty, he gives an account closely resembling the analysis that, according to MacCallum and his numerous followers, must be given of any claim about freedom if it is to be intelligible.
Keywords: PHILOSOPHY ; Sociology
[25] AJohn Simmons. Justification and Legitimacy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2001.
A. John Simmons is widely regarded as one of the most innovative and creative of today's political philosophers. His work on political obligation is regarded as definitive and he is also internationally respected as an interpreter of John Locke. The characteristic features of clear argumentation and careful scholarship that have been hallmarks of his philosophy are everywhere evident in this collection. The essays focus on the problems of political obligation and state legitimacy as well as on historical theories of property and justice. Cumulatively the collection presents a distinctive social and political philosophy, exploring the nature of our most fundamental rights and obligations, and displaying the power and plausibility of Lockean ideal theory.
Keywords: Political obligation ; Legitimacy of governments ; Human rights
[26] Bernard Williams. Moral luck. Cambridge University Press, 2013.
A new volume of philosophical essays by Bernard Williams. The book is a successor to Problems of the Self, but whereas that volume dealt mainly with questions of personal identity, Moral Luck centres on questions of moral philosophy and the theory of rational action. That whole area has of course been strikingly reinvigorated over the last deacde, and philosophers have both broadened and deepened their concerns in a way that now makes much earlier moral and political philosophy look sterile and trivial. Moral Luck contains a number of essays that have contributed influentially to this development. Among the recurring themes are the moral and philosophical limitations of utilitarianism, the notion of integrity, relativism, and problems of moral conflict and rational choice. The work presented here is marked by a high degree of imagination and acuity, and also conveys a strong sense of psychological reality. The volume will be a stimulating source of ideas and arguments for all philosophers and a wide range of other readers.
Keywords: Ethics
[27] Paul Sagar. Politics Recovered, chapter Legitimacy and Domination. Columbia University Press, New York, 1 edition, 2018.
Is political theory political enough? Or does a tendency toward abstraction, idealization, moralism, and utopianism leave contemporary political theory out of touch with real politics as it actually takes place, and hence unable to speak meaningfully to or about our world? Realist political thought, which has enjoyed a significant revival of interest in recent years, seeks to avoid such pitfalls by remaining attentive to the distinctiveness of politics and the ways its realities ought to shape how we think and act in the political realm.Politics Recoveredbrings together prominent scholars to develop what it might mean to theorize politics "realistically." Intervening in philosophical debates such as the relationship between politics and morality and the role that facts and emotions should play in the theorization of political values, the volume addresses how a realist approach aids our understanding of pressing issues such as global justice, inequality, poverty, political corruption, the value of democracy, governmental secrecy, and demands for transparency. Contributors open up fruitful dialogues with a variety of other realist approaches, such as feminist theory, democratic theory, and international relations. By exploring the nature and prospects of realist thought,Politics Recoveredshows how political theory can affirm reality in order to provide meaningful and compelling answers to the fundamental questions of political life.
Keywords: Philosophy ; Political realism ; POLITICAL SCIENCE
[28] Istvan Hont. Adam smith's history of law and government as political theory. In Political Judgement, pages 131--171. Cambridge University Press, 2009.
The burden of judgement: Dunn, Kant and LockeIn all his work John Dunn has insisted that political judgement must be regarded as a central issue of political theory. Nonetheless, only a few political theorists work explicitly on this topic. Among them Dunn is perhaps the only one who stands entirely outside the Kantian tradition. This is a striking fact, for Kant's contribution is widely regarded as foundational for the understanding of judgement (moral, aesthetic and political) in modern thought. Judgement is usually defined with reference to Kant's pithy characterisation of it in his Critique of Judgment as `the ability to think the particular as contained under the universal', as the link between theory and practice. `It is obvious', Kant claimed in his essay `On the common saying: That may be correct in theory, but it is of no use in practice', that `between theory and practice there is required ... a middle term connecting them and providing a transition from one to the other', an `act of judgment by which a practitioner distinguishes whether or not something is a case of the rule'.Kant's essay conveyed a double-edged message about the problem of judgement. At first Kant asserted that there was an ineliminable gap between theory and practice which could not be closed by developing a theory of judgement. Judgement as such could have no rule, for a rule was precisely a theory, requiring a further judgement for its implementation as practice. This would lead to infinite regress. In Kantian terms, a theory of judgement was an oxymoron.
[29] Immanuel Kant. Practical philosophy. The Cambridge edition of the works of Immanuel Kant. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1996.
This 1997 book was the first English translation of all of Kant's writings on moral and political philosophy collected in a single volume. No other collection competes with the comprehensiveness of this one. As well as Kant's most famous moral and political writings, the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, the Critique of Practical Reason, the Metaphysics of Morals, and Toward Perpetual Peace, the volume includes shorter essays and reviews, some of which have never been translated before. The volume has been furnished with a substantial editorial apparatus including translator's introductions and explanatory notes to each text by Mary Gregor, and a general introduction to Kant's moral and political philosophy by Allen Wood. There is also an English-German and German-English glossary of key terms.
Keywords: Ethics Modern -- 18th century
[30] AJohn. Simmons. The Lockean Theory of Rights. Studies in moral, political, and legal philosophy. University Press, Princeton (New Jersey), [1st publ. in paperback]. edition, 1994.
John Locke's political theory has been the subject of many detailed treatments by philosophers and political scientists. But The Lockean Theory of Rights is the first systematic, full-length study of Locke's theory of rights and of its potential for making genuine contributions to contemporary debates about rights and their place in political philosophy. Given that the rights of persons are the central moral concept at work in Locke's and Lockean political philosophy, such a study is long overdue.
Keywords: Derecho -- Filosofía ; Locke John -- Crítica e interpretación
[31] Ineke Sluiter, Lucien van Beek, Ton Kessels, and Albert Rijksbaron. Woordenboek Grieks/Nederlands. Amsterdam University Press, 1 edition, 2024.
[32] Immanuel Kant. Critique of judgement. Oxford world's classics. Oxford University Press, Oxford ;, 2007.
Kant's Critique of Judgement analyses our experience of the beautiful and the sublime in relation to nature, morality, and theology. Meredith's classic translation is here lightly revised and supplemented with a bilingual glossary. The edition also includes the important First Introduction. - ;'beauty has purport and significance only for human beings, for beings at once animal and rational'. In the Critique of Judgement (1790) Kant offers a penetrating analysis of our experience of the beautiful and the sublime, discussing the objectivity of taste, aesthetic disinterestedness, the relation of
Keywords: Judgment (Logic) ; Judgment (Aesthetics) ; Teleology
[33] Dudley Knowles. Political Obligation: A Critical Introduction. Routledge Contemporary Political Philosophy. Routledge, Oxford, 1 edition, 2010.
Political obligation is concerned with the clash between the individual's claim to self-governance and the right of the state to claim obedience. It is a central and ancient problem in political philosophy. In this authoritative introduction, Dudley Knowles frames the problem of obligation in terms of the duties citizens have to the state and each other. Drawing on a wide range of key works in political philosophy, from Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, David Hume and G. W. F. Hegel to John Rawls, A. John Simmons, Joseph Raz and Ronald Dworkin, Political Obligation: A Critical Introduction is an ideal starting point for those coming to the topic for the first time, as well as being an original and distinctive contribution to the literature. Knowles distinguishes the philosophical problem of obligation - which types of argument may successfully ground the legitimacy of the state and the duties of citizens - from the political problem of obligation - whether successful arguments apply to the actual citizens of particular states. Against the anarchist and modern skeptics, Knowles claims that a plurality of arguments promise success when carefully formulated and defended, and discusses in turn ancient and modern theories of social contract and consent, fairness and gratitude, utilitarianism, justice and a Samaritan duty of care for others. Against modern communitarians, he defends a distinctive liberalism: `the state proposes, the citizen disposes'. Dudley Knowles is Professor of Political Philosophy at the University of Glasgow. He is the author of Political Philosophy and Hegel's Philosophy of Right , also published by Routledge, as well as many articles.
Keywords: Political obligation ; Political Theory ; Political Philosophy ; Political science ; Textbooks
[34] Paul Sagar. The opinion of mankind : sociability and the theory of the state from Hobbes to Smith. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ, 2018.
Keywords: Hobbes Thomas 1588-1679 ; Hume David 1711-1776 ; Smith Adam 1723-1790 ; Political science -- History ; POLITICAL SCIENCE / Essays ; POLITICAL SCIENCE / Government / General ; POLITICAL SCIENCE / Government / National ; POLITICAL SCIENCE / Reference ; Political science ; State The ; 89.06 political philosophy
[35] John Rawls and Erin. Kelly. Justice as fairness : a restatement. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Mass, 2001.
This book originated as lectures for a course on political philosophy that Rawls taught regularly at Harvard in the 1980s. In time the lectures became a restatement of his theory of justice as fairness, revised in light of his more recent papers and his treatise Political Liberalism (1993). Rawls offers a broad overview of his main lines of thought and also explores specific issues never before addressed in any of his writings. He is well aware that since the publication of A Theory of Justice in 1971, American society has moved farther away from the idea of justice as fairness. Yet his ideas retain their power and relevance to debates in a pluralistic society about the meaning and theoretical viability of liberalism. This book demonstrates that moral clarity can be achieved even when a collective commitment to justice is uncertain.
Keywords: Impartialité ; POLITICAL SCIENCE -- Essays ; POLITICAL SCIENCE -- Government -- General ; POLITICAL SCIENCE -- Government -- National ; POLITICAL SCIENCE -- Reference ; Justice sociale ; Théorie politique ; Equité ; Fairness ; Justice ; Rechtvaardigheid ; Justiça (aspectos políticos)
[36] John Dunn. The Political Thought of John Locke: An Historical Account of the Argument of the 'Two Treatises of Government'. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1969.
This study provides a comprehensive reinterpretation of the meaning of Locke's political thought. John Dunn restores Locke's ideas to their exact context, and so stresses the historical question of what Locke in the Two Treatises of Government was intending to claim. By adopting this approach, he reveals the predominantly theological character of all Locke's thinking about politics and provides a convincing analysis of the development of Locke's thought. In a polemical concluding section, John Dunn argues that liberal and Marxist interpretations of Locke's politics have failed to grasp his meaning. Locke emerges as not merely a contributor to the development of English constitutional thought, or as a reflector of socio-economic change in seventeenth-century England, but as essentially a Calvinist natural theologian.
Keywords: Political science
[37] William Temple. Observations upon the United Provinces of the Netherlands By Sir William Temple .... printed for Jacob Tonson, and Awnsham and John Churchill, London, the seventh edition. corrected and augmented. edition, 1705.
[38] Richard Whatmore. The End of Enlightenment. Penguin Random House UK, 2023.
[39] Reinhart Koselleck. Critique and Crisis. MIT Press, 1998.
[40] Allen Rosen. Kant's Theory of Justice. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY, 1st ed. edition, 2018.
In this accessible interpretation of Kant's political philosophy, Allen D. Rosen concentrates on the relation between justice, political authority (the state), and individual liberty.
Keywords: Social ethics ; State The ; Liberty ; Kant Immanuel 1724-1804 -- Political and social views
[41] Craig L. Carr. Kant's theory of political authority. History of political thought, X(4):719--731, 1989.
Keywords: Political authority ; Immanuel Kant
[42] David Hume. A Treatise of Human Nature, volume 1. Clarendon, Oxford, 2007.
"A Treatise of Human Nature" by David Hume is a philosophical work written in the early 18th century. The book seeks to explore the underlying principles of human nature, with a focus on understanding the origin and workings of human thoughts and emotions. Hume delves into various topics of human experience, highlighting the relationship between impressions and ideas, and how these elements contribute to our understanding of reality. The opening of the treatise introduces Hume's approach, emphasizing that all perceptions in the human mind consist of two distinct types: impressions, which are vivid and forceful, and ideas, which are their fainter representations. Hume proposes to categorize these perceptions and elucidate their qualities and relationships, especially focusing on how simple ideas derive from simple impressions. He aims to establish a foundational understanding of human nature that connects ideas and their origins, while also hinting at the broader implications this understanding may have on other branches like ethics and social philosophy. (This is an automatically generated summary.)
[43] Horacio Spector. Hume's theory of justice. Rationality, Markets and Morals, 5, 2014.
[44] Raymond B. Marcin. Schopenhauer's theory of justice. Catholic University Law Review, 43(3), 1994.
[45] Jean-Jacques Rousseau and Martin McQuillan. Essay on the origin of language: Melody and musical imitation are being considered. In The Paul De Man Notebooks, pages 183--224. Edinburgh University Press, United Kingdom, 2014.
Of the Various Means of Conveying One's ThoughtsSpeech sets man apart among animals, language distinguishes between nations: one knows where a man comes from only after he has spoken. Usage and need make that everyone learns the language of his country; but what is it that makes this language the language of his country and not of another? In order to tell, one must go back to an explanation that belongs specifically to the place and that predates even the local customs: speech, the first institution of society, owes its shape only to natural causes.As soon as man was recognized by another similar to himself, as a being capable of feeling and of thought, the desire or the need to convey his feelings and his thoughts put him in search of the means to do so. These means could only stem from the senses, the only instruments through which a man can act upon another man. Hence the institution of sensory signs in order to express thought. The inventors of language did not reason this way, but instinct suggested this conclusion to them.The general means by which we can act upon someone's senses are limited to two, namely motion and voice. The effect of motion is immediate in the case of touch or mediate in the case of gesture. Since the first is restricted by the length of one's arm it cannot communicate at a distance, but the other can reach as far as a lightning ray can travel.
Keywords: Language ; Acoustics ; Animals ; Anthropology ; Applied sciences ; Articulatory phonetics ; Arts ; Behavioral sciences ; Biological sciences ; Biology ; Colors ; Communications ; Dialectology ; Dialects ; Ethnolinguistics ; Ethnology ; Gestures ; harmony ; Humans ; Jean-Jacques Rousseau ; Linguistics ; Literary genres ; Literary studies: general ; Literary theory ; Literary Theory and Cultural Studies ; Literature ; Mammals ; Material properties ; Materials science ; Melody ; Music ; Music theory ; Musical chords ; Musical pitch ; Nonverbal communication ; Optical properties ; Paul de Man ; Performing arts ; Phonetics ; Phonology ; Physical sciences ; Physics ; Poetry ; political government ; Primates ; prosody ; Regional dialects ; Social sciences ; Sound ; speech ; Tonal harmony ; Tonal theory ; Voiced sounds ; writing ; Zoology
[46] David Hume, Angela Coventry, and Andrew Valls. Of the origin of government. In David Hume on Morals, Politics, and Society, pages 151--154. Yale University Press, New Haven, 2018.
[47] Istvan Hont. Politics in Commercial Society. Harvard University Press, 2 edition, 2015.
[48] Jean-Jacques Rousseau. The second discourse: Discourse on the origin and foundations of inequality among mankind. In The Social Contract and The First and Second Discourses, pages 69--. Yale University Press, 2002.
Convinced that it belongs only to a virtuous citizen to present his country those acknowledgments it may become her to receive, I have been for thirty years past, endeavoring to render myself worthy to offer you some public homage. In the meantime, this fortunate occasion replacing in some degree the insufficiency of my efforts, I have presumed rather to follow the dictates of zeal, than to wait till I should be authorized by merit. Having had the good fortune to be born a subject of Geneva, how could I reflect on the natural equality of mankind, and that inequality which
Keywords: Animals ; Anthropology ; Behavioral sciences ; Biological sciences ; Biology ; Children ; Countries ; Environmental sciences ; Environmental studies ; Epistemology ; Government ; Government officials ; Human geography ; Human populations ; Humanity ; Humans ; Judges ; Judicial officers ; Jurisprudence ; Law ; Magistrates ; Mammals ; Natural law ; Nature ; Persons ; Philosophical anthropology ; Philosophy ; Philosophy of law ; Political geography ; Political philosophy ; Political science ; Population studies ; Primates ; Social contract ; Social sciences ; State of nature ; Wisdom ; Zoology
[49] Adam Smith. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Gutenberg, 2022.
[50] Jean-Jacques Rousseau. Émile, ou de l'éducation. Project Gutenberg, Salt Lake City, UT, 2004.
"Emile" by Jean-Jacques Rousseau is a philosophical treatise on education, likely written in the late 18th century. The work explores Rousseau's thoughts on how children should be raised and educated, emphasizing the need to align educational practices with natural development rather than societal norms. Central to the text is the character of Emile, an imaginary pupil who undergoes a unique form of upbringing that cultivates his natural goodness and capacities. The opening of "Emile" introduces Rousseau's aims for the book, explaining his departure from traditional educational approaches. He expresses his belief that conventional methods are flawed and do not account for the essence of a child's nature or their potential for learning. Rousseau critiques societal influences that corrupt the inherent goodness of children and argues for a nurturing approach that respects their development. He presents a vision for education focused on understanding the child's needs and nature, suggesting that personal and experiential learning should take precedence over rote memorization and formal instruction. This foundational philosophy sets the stage for the detailed explorations of Emile's upbringing that follow in the text. (This is an automatically generated summary.)
[51] David Hume. An enquiry concerning the principles of morals By David Hume, Esq. printed for A. Millar, London, 1751.
Keywords: Ethics ; 1700-1800 ; 08.24 newer western philosophy (17-19th century) ; 08.38 ethics
[52] Samuel Pufendorf, Ian Hunter, David Saunders, and Jean Barbeyrac. The whole duty of man according to the law of nature. Natural law and enlightenment classics. Liberty Fund, Indianapolis, Ind, 2003.
Keywords: Natural law ; Ethics ; State The
[53] Cara Nine. Sharing Territories: Overlapping Self-Determination and Resource Rights. New Topics in Applied Philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1 edition, 2022.
Territorial rights are shared between overlapping political units, not exclusively held by states. This book takes this claim to be both an empirical observation and a philosophical goal. A theory of territorial rights should be able to inform the normative relationship between overlapping territorial units. In order to do this, Nine's view defends a river model of territorial rights. On a river model, political units are assumed to be interdependent and overlapping. This model stands in contrast to the prevailing desert island model, where political units are assumed to be independent and distinct from each other. Drawing on Pufendorf's natural law philosophy and feminist theory, Nine's view argues for the establishment of foundational territories around geographical areas like rivers. Usually lower-scale political entities, foundational territories overlap with and serve as grounding blocks of larger territorial units. Examples of foundational territories include not just river catchment areas but also urban areas, drawn around individuals who hold obligations to collectively manage their surroundings together. Foundational territorial authorities manage spatially integrated areas where agents are interconnected by dense and scaffolded physical circumstances. In these areas, individuals cannot fulfil their natural obligations to each other without the help of collective rules. Because foundational territories overlap the territories of other political units, this book frames a theory of nested and shared territorial rights.
Keywords: Boundaries ; Jurisdiction Territorial ; Natural law ; Natural law-Religious aspects ; Social and Political Philosophy
[54] Samuel Pufendorf. Of the law of nature and nations. Eight books. Written in Latin by the Baron Pufendorf, Counsellor of State to his late Swedish Majesty, and to the late King of Prussia. Done into English by Basil Kennett D. D. late President of Corpus Christi College in Oxford. To which are added all the large notes of Mr. Barbeyrac, translated from the best edition; Together with Large tables to the Whole. The fourth edition, carefully corrected. To which is now prefixed Mr. Barbeyrac's prefatory discourse, containing An Historical and Critical Account of the Science of Morality, and the Progress it has made in the World, from the earliest Times down to the Publication of this Work. Done into English by Mr. Carew of Lincoln's-Inn. S. Aris for J. Walthoe, R. Wilkin, J. and J. Bonwicke, S. Birt, T. Ward, and T. Osborne, London, 1729.
Keywords: International law; Books; Natural law
[55] Karen Stohr. Kantian beneficence and the problem of obligatory aid. Journal of moral philosophy, 8(1):45--67, 2011.
Keywords: BENEFICENCE ; BARBARA HERMAN ; IMPERFECT DUTY ; KANT ; LATITUDE ; OBLIGATION ; THOMAS HILL
[56] Ruth. Lorand. Aesthetic theory : a philosophy of beauty and art. Routledge studies in twentieth century philosophy. Routledge, London ;, 1st ed. edition, 2000.
Aesthetic Order challenges contemporary theories of aesthetics, offering the idea of beauty as quantitative yet different from the traditional discursive order. It will be of importance to all interested in aesthetic theory.
Keywords: Aesthetics ; Philosophy
[57] Charles Tilly, Gabriel. Ardant, and Social Science Research CouncilCommittee on Comparative Politics. The formation of national states in Western Europe. Studies in political development, 8. Princeton University Press, Princeton, N. J, 1975.
Keywords: Staat ; Entstehung ; Aufsatzsammlung ; Nationalstaat ; Nationalisme -- Histoire -- Europe de l'Ouest ; Nationalités -- Histoire -- Europe de l'Ouest ; Nation ; État ; Formation of government ; Europe Politics ; Western Europe ; 89.31 state (political science)
[58] Jeremy Waldron. The advantages and difficulties of the humean theory of property. Social philosophy & policy, 11(2):85--123, 1994.
In recent years there has been growing interest in the contrast between Humean theories of property, on the one hand, and Lockean and Rousseauian theories, on the other. The contrast is a broad and abstract one, along the following lines.
Keywords: Property rights ; David Hume ; Philosophical aspects
[59] James McGill Buchanan. The limits of liberty: between anarchy and Leviathan. Phoenix books ; nr. 714. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1975.
Keywords: Liberty ; State The ; Freedom of conscience ; Constitutions ; Social contract ; 89.42 internal relations of the state with civilians
[60] David Miller. Territorial rights: Concept and justification. Political studies, 60(2):252--268, 2012.
This article begins by analysing the idea of territorial rights. It argues that the rights over territory standardly claimed by states can be separated into three main elements: the right of jurisdiction, the right to the territory's resources and the right to control borders. A full justification of territorial rights must therefore address each of these three elements. It proceeds to examine theories that treat states as the primary holders of territorial rights. Utilitarian theories (such as Sidgwick's) maintain that states acquire such rights simply by maintaining social order over the relevant territory. Such theories are insufficiently discriminating and cannot deal adequately with the issues raised by invasion and secession. An alternative view adds the condition that the state must be the legitimate representative of the people who (innocently) occupy the territory, but this too faces an objection. A historical version of the statist theory claims that states gain territorial rights by increasing the value of territory over time, but such historical entitlement theories are implausible in the case of states. In contrast, the article argues that an adequate justificatory theory of territorial rights must treat peoples -- nations or indigenous groups -- as the primary bearers of these rights. Peoples gain such rights by adding material value to the territory in question, and endowing it with symbolic value. After responding to objections from global egalitarians and others, the article concludes that such a justificatory theory can unite the three elements of territorial rights distinguished at the outset.
Keywords: rights ; Borders ; Civil rights ; Colonies & territories ; Culture ; Indigenous Populations ; Jurisdiction ; nation ; Political rights ; Secession ; Social Order ; state ; States ; Statism ; Territoriality ; Territory ; Utilitarianism
[61] Anna Stilz. Territory and self-determination. Annual review of political science, 27(1):337--354, 2024.
This article focuses on discussions of territorial rights and self-determination in the last 15--20 years. Theories of territorial jurisdiction typically combine two elements. First, they offer an account of foundational title: What gives a particular set of people a claim to be located in an area, including the right to form political institutions to govern that space? Second, they offer an account of legitimate jurisdiction: What is the moral basis of a state's right to govern the area and its population? This article begins by reconstructing prominent accounts of foundational title and legitimate jurisdiction. After canvassing these views, I highlight three areas where further work is needed, particularly as the territorial states system begins to be challenged by climate change: the appropriate balance of sovereignty and international authority in a world of global interdependence, how to rectify imperial and colonial legacies in the states system, and the just distribution of territory.
Keywords: Self determination ; self-determination ; Climate change ; colonialism ; Colonies & territories ; Interdependence ; Jurisdiction ; Political institutions ; Sovereignty ; State ; territory
[62] Arthur Ripstein. Force and Freedom. Harvard University Press, 2010.
In this masterful work, both an illumination of Kant's thought and an important contribution to contemporary legal and political theory, Arthur Ripstein gives a comprehensive yet accessible account of Kant's political philosophy. In addition to providing a clear and coherent statement of the most misunderstood of Kant's ideas, Ripstein also shows that Kant's views remain conceptually powerful and morally appealing today.
Keywords: Kant Immanuel 1724--1804 ; Law ; Philosophy ; Political and social views ; Political Science
[63] Arthur Hill. Debate: Political authority, functionalism, and the problem of annexation. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 2023.
Keywords: functionalism, annexation, territory
[64] Anna Stilz. Territorial Sovereignty. Oxford political theory. Academic and Trade, Oxford, England, new product edition. edition, 2019.
Territorial Sovereignty: A Philosophical Exploration offers a qualified defense of a territorial states-system. It argues that three core values-occupancy, basic justice, and collective self-determination-are served by an international system made up of self-governing, spatially defined political units. The defense is qualified because the book does not actually justify all the sovereignty rights states currently claim, and that are recognized in international law. Instead, the book proposes important changes to states' sovereign prerogatives, particularly with respect to internal autonomy for political minorities, immigration, and natural resources. Part I of the book argues for a right of occupancy, holding that a legitimate function of the international system is to specify and protect people's preinstitutional claims to specific geographical places. Part II turns to the question of how a state might acquire legitimate jurisdiction over a population of occupants. It argues that the state will have a right to rule a population and its territory if it satisfies conditions of basic justice and also facilitates its people's collective self-determination. Finally, Parts III and IV of this book argue that the exclusionary sovereignty rights to control over borders and natural resources that can plausibly be justified on the basis of the three core values are more limited than has traditionally been thought. Oxford Political Theory presents the best new work in contemporary political theory. It is intended to be broad in scope, including original contributions to political philosophy, and also work in applied political theory. The series will contain works of outstanding quality with no restriction as to approach or subject matter.
Keywords: Sovereignty -- Philosophy
[65] Margaret Moore. A political theory of territory. Oxford Political Philosophy. Oxford University Press, New York, 2015.
This title offers a political self-determination theory of territory. Territorial disputes are at the centre of some of the most intractable controversies facing us today but it is also one of the most under-theorised concepts that we rely on. Most work in political philosophy, international relations, political science, and law take for granted the territorial imperative (that we need states, and states are necessarily territorial); yet, this book argues, territory itself requires a defence.
Keywords: Territory National -- Philosophy ; Jurisdiction Territorial -- Philosophy ; State The -- Philosophy
[66] AJohn Simmons. Boundaries of Authority. Oxford University Press, New York, 1 edition, 2016.
Modern states claim rights of jurisdiction and control over particular geographical areas and their associated natural resources. Boundaries of Authority explores the possible moral bases for such territorial claims by states. The book maintains throughout that the requirement of states' justified authority over persons has normative priority over, and as a result severely restricts, the kinds of territorial rights that states can justifiably claim, and it argues that the mere effective administration of justice within a geographical area is insufficient to ground moral authority over residents of that area. The book argues that only a theory of territorial rights that takes seriously the morality of the actual history of states' acquisitions of power over land and the land's residents can adequately explain the nature and extent of states' moral rights over particular territories. Part I of the book examines the interconnections between states' claimed rights of authority over particular sets of subject persons and states' claimed authority to control particular territories. Part II organizes, explains, and criticizes the full range of extant theories of states' territorial rights, arguing that a little-appreciated Lockean approach to territorial rights is in fact far better able to meet the principal desiderata for such theories. Part III of the book looks closely at the more property-like territorial rights that states claim---in particular, their claimed rights to control over the natural resources in and around their territories and their claimed rights to control and restrict movement across (including immigration over) their territorial borders.
Keywords: Philosophy ; Social and Political Philosophy ; Territory National
[67] Peter Pan Records. Superman - the man from krypton - part ii. [ http ]
[68] Timmie Rogers. The black astronauts. [ http ]
[69] John F. Kennedy. We choose to go to the moon. [ http ]
[70] John Dankworth. Two piece flower. [ http ]
[71] Gottfried Wilhelm Freiherr von Leibniz and Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra. Leibniz : discourse on metaphysics. Leibniz from Oxford. Oxford University Press, Oxford, England, first edition. edition, 2020.
Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereya provides a new English translation of G.W. Leibniz's 'Discourse on Metaphysics', complete with a critical introduction and a comprehensive philosophical commentary. In this fundamental work, Leibniz sets out a metaphysics for Christianity and provides answers to the central metaphysical questions.
Keywords: Metaphysics ; Leibniz Gottfried Wilhelm 1646-1716 Petit discours de métaphysique
[72] Richard Halpern. Leibnizing. Columbia University Press, 2023.
[73] Gang Starr. Above the clouds. [ http ]
[74] Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. Philosophical Papers and Letters. Springer, 1989.
[75] Martijn Boven. Towards a theory of the imaginative dialogue: Four dialogical principles. Studies in Philosophy and Education, 43, 2024.
[76] Jacob T. Levy. The liberal defence of democracy: A critique of pettit. Australian Journal of Political Science, 29(3), 1994. [ http ]
[77] Kenneth Novis. Negative dialectics before object-oriented philosophy: negation and event. Open Philosophy, 3, 2020.
[78] Graham Harman. Object-oriented ontology. Pelican Books, 2018.
[79] Pete Wolfendale. Object-oriented philosophy. Urbanomic, Falmouth, United Kingdom, 2014.
Keywords: Object (Philosophy) ; Ontology
[80] Graham Harman. After finitude. In Quentin Meillassoux, pages 6--53. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh, 2022.
[81] Graham Harman. On truth and lie in the object-oriented sense. Open Philosophy, 5, 2022.
[82] J.G. Fichte. The science of knowledge. Cambridge University Press, 1991.
[83] Immanuel Kant. Critique of pure reason. Cambridge University Press, 1998.
[84] William C. Mattison. Movements of love: A thomistic perspective on agape and eros. Journal of Moral Theology, 1(2), 2012.
[85] Arthur Schopenhauer. The basis of morality. Swan Sonnenschein, 1903.
[86] Robert D. Enright, Jiahe Wang Xu, Hannah Rapp, Moon Evans, Jacqueline Y. Song, James Cresswell, and Bruce Jennings. The philosophy and social science of agape love. Journal of theoretical and philosophical psychology, 42(4):220--237, 2022.
The moral virtues have had prominence in social scientific research ever since Piaget's (1932) and Kohlberg's (1969) pioneering work on the cognitive developmental stages of justice reasoning. A less explored moral virtue is the ancient idea of agape, or love that is in service to others which includes effort and even pain on the part of the one expressing the virtue. In this work, we attempt a precise definition of agape using Aristotelian philosophical views of virtue ethics and his principles of analyzing constructs for their essences and their specific differences with related but distinct constructs. From this Aristotelian philosophical framework, we then critique existing social scientific measures of love and of agape in particular. We then provide guidelines for the development of construct-valid measures of agape that are philosophically coherent. Possible research questions to expand the scientific study of agape are presented as a way forward with this important construct that could bring psychological health to individuals and peace and unity to families and communities. Public Significance Statement Agape love is a moral virtue in which a person willingly and unconditionally offers goodness, at a cost to the giver, to another or others in need. Because this under-researched ancient concept has implications for harmonious relationships and for good mental health, accurate measures of agape are needed to assess the degree to which a person understands and practices it.
Keywords: Human ; Justice ; Love ; Morality ; Philosophers ; Philosophies ; Social Justice ; Social Sciences ; Virtue
[87] Anders Nygren. Agape and eros. The Westminster Press, 1930.
[88] Michael S. Batts, Danielle Buschinger, Marion E. Gibbs, Nigel Harris, Sidney M. Johnson, Ulrich Mueller, Ann Marie Rasmussen, Daniel Rocher, Adrian Stevens, and Neil Thomas. A Companion to Gottfried von Strassburg's Tristan. Studies in German Literature Linguistics and Culture. Boydell and Brewer, 2003.
[89] Rosalind Field. Popular Romance: The Material and the Problems, pages 9--30. Studies in Medieval Romance. Boydell and Brewer, 2009.
[90] Will Hasty. Chapter Six Love and Adventure in Germany: The Romances of Hartmann von Aue, Wolfram von Eschenbach, and Gottfried von Straßburg, pages 215 -- 287. Brill, 2002. [ DOI | http ]
[91] Francis Gentry. A Companion to Middle High German Literature to the 14th century. Brill, Leiden, The Netherlands, 2002. [ DOI | http ]
[92] JD. Burnley. Fine amor: Its meaning and context. The Review of English Studies, 31(122):129--148, 1980. [ http ]
[93] Heli Tissari. Affection, friendship, passion and charity: A history of four "love lexemes" since the fifteenth century. Neuphilologische Mitteilungen, 102(1):49--76, 2001. [ http ]
This article discusses the affinities and differences between four lexemes related to LOVE and the lexeme LOVE itself over a time span of roughly six hundred years, comparing earlier usage (1417-1710) with Present-Day English. The approach is prototype-semantic, and the data consists of four English language corpora. They are the Early Modern English period of the Helsinki Corpus of English Texts (HC), the electronic Oxford edition of Shakespeare's Complete Works (SH), the Corpus of Early English Correspondence Sampler (CEECS) and the British National Corpus (BNC). The Oxford English Dictionary (OED) and the Historical Thesaurus of English (HTE) were also consulted. It is possible to detect two kinds of change in the usage of the four lexemes. Firstly, if the dictionary senses are treated as prototypical categories, we can see the meanings of the lexemes change via processes of inductive generalisation, specialisation, metonymy and metaphor. Secondly, if we look at these lexemes differently and consider the appearance of the categories of family love (storge), friendship (philia), romantic and sexual love (eros), married love (storge-eros), religious love (agape) and love of things (khreia), we can again see changes in their meanings between the two periods.
[94] John C. Moore. "courtly love": A problem of terminology. Journal of the History of Ideas, 40(4), 1979. [ http ]
[95] Gottfried von Straßburg. Tristan. Penguin Group, 2 edition, 1984.
[96] Denis de Rougemont. Love in the western world. Princeton University Press, 1983.
[97] John Rutherford. The Troubadours. Smith, Elder, Co., 1873.
[98] Joseph C. Mihalich. Marcel's ontology of love. Renascence, 13(1):21, Fall 1960. Last updated - 2013-02-21.
Keywords: Humanities (General)
[99] Thomas C. Leonard. Illiberal Reformers. Princeton University Press, fourth edition, 2017.
Keywords: eugenics, progressivism, Gilded Age
[100] Walter Lippmann. Public opinion. Routledge, second edition, 1998.
[101] Wilfred Trotter. Instincts of the herd in peace and war. T. Fisher Unwin Ltd, first edition, February 1916.
[102] Michal Kosinski, David Stillwell, and Thore Graepel. Private traits and attributes are predictable from digital records of human behavior. PNAS, 110(15), April 2013.
Keywords: social neworks; computational social science; machine learning; big data; data mining; psychological assessment
[103] Rand Fishkin. An anonymous source shared thousands of leaked google search api documents with me; everyone in seo should see them. https://sparktoro.com/blog/an-anonymous-source-shared-thousands-of-leaked-google-search-api-documents-with-me-everyone-in-seo-should-see-them/, May 2024. [ http ]
Keywords: google search; leak
[104] Edward Bernays. Crystallizing public opinion. Ig Publishing, 2011.
Keywords: propaganda
[105] Edward Bernays. Propaganda. Ig Publishing, first edition, 2005.
Keywords: propaganda
[106] Nick Fischer. The committee on public information and the birth of us state propaganda. Australasian Journal of American Studies, 35(1), July 2016.
Keywords: propaganda
[107] Amnesty International. Uk: Europe's top court rules uk mass surveillance regime violated human rights. https://www.amnesty.org/en/latest/press-release/2021/05/uk-surveillance-gchq-ecthr-ruling/, 05 2021. [ http ]
Keywords: GCHQ
[108] Gustave Le Bon. The crowd. Dover publications, Mineola, New York, 2015.
[109] Max Horkheimer. Critical Theory. Continuum Publishing, 2002.
[110] CWright Mills. The power elite. Oxford University Press, first edition, 1959.
Keywords: sociology; philosophy
[111] David M Estlund. Democratic authority: a philosophical framework. Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1 edition, 2009.
Democracy is not naturally plausible. Why turn such important matters over to masses of people who have no expertise? Many theories of democracy answer by appealing to the intrinsic value of democratic procedure, leaving aside whether it makes good decisions. In Democratic Authority, David Estlund offers a groundbreaking alternative based on the idea that democratic authority and legitimacy must depend partly on democracy's tendency to make good decisions. Just as with verdicts in jury trials, Estlund argues, the authority and legitimacy of a political decision does not depend on the particular decision being good or correct. But the "epistemic value" of the procedure--the degree to which it can generally be accepted as tending toward a good decision--is nevertheless crucial. Yet if good decisions were all that mattered, one might wonder why those who know best shouldn't simply rule.
Keywords: American Government ; Authority ; Democracy ; History & Theory ; Judicial Branch ; Philosophy ; POLITICAL SCIENCE
[112] Thomas Christiano. The authority of democracy. The journal of political philosophy, 12(3):266--290, 2004.
A justification for maintaining the legitimacy of democratic decision making is offered. A dualistic account of democracy based upon two principles -- democracy promotes the equal advancement of all interests & social justice must be visible within democracy -- is proposed. After relating the formal & substantive arguments for conceptualizing social justice in such a manner, it is asserted that democratic decision making is fully capable of providing for the equitable advancement of competing interests in a publicly transparent way. It is subsequently argued that the legitimacy of democratic decision making is contingent upon the fairness of the substance of democratic laws or the justness of democratic processes. Moreover, it is stressed that democratic authority must take public perspectives into account to further legitimize democratic decision making. A hypothetical scenario in which the national legislature supports discriminatory enfranchisement laws is then used to determine the conditions under restraints should be placed upon democratic authority. It is concluded that a democracy's loss of its intrinsic sense of justice signals the de-legitimatization of democratic authority. J. W. Parker
Keywords: Authority ; Decision Making ; Democracy ; Equality ; Ethics ; Government & Law ; Legitimacy ; Political Science ; Political theory ; Public Opinion ; Social Justice ; Social Sciences ; Social Sciences - Other Topics
[113] Ruth Gavison. Privacy and the limits of law. The Yale law journal, 89(3), 1980.
This article identifies the concept of privacy and legal system committed to such a value.
Keywords: Analysis ; CIVIL RIGHTS, CIVIL LIBERTIES, CONTEMPORARY CIVIL RIGHTS MOVEMENTS ; Human relations ; Information legislation ; Intimacy ; Invasion of privacy ; Jurisprudence ; LAW AND LEGAL SYSTEMS ; Mental health ; Plaintiffs ; PRIVACY ; PRIVACY AND ITS INVASION ; Privacy rights ; Privacy, Right of ; Reductionism ; Right to privacy ; Torts ; US POLITICAL INSTITUTIONS, PROCESSES & BEHAVIOR
[114] Vikram R. Bhargava and Manuel Velasquez. Ethics of the attention economy. Business ethics quarterly, 31(3), 2021.
Social media companies commonly design their platforms in a way that renders them addictive. Some governments have declared internet addiction a major public health concern, and the World Health Organization has characterized excessive internet use as a growing problem. Our article shows why scholars, policy makers, and the managers of social media companies should treat social media addiction as a serious moral problem. While the benefits of social media are not negligible, we argue that social media addiction raises unique ethical concerns not raised by other, more familiar addictive products, such as alcohol and cigarettes. In particular, we argue that addicting users to social media is impermissible because it unjustifiably harms users in a way that is both demeaning and objectionably exploitative. Importantly, the attention-economy business model of social media companies strongly incentivizes them to perpetrate this wrongdoing.
Keywords: Addictions ; Addictive behaviors ; Attention ; Business models ; Cigarettes ; Design ; Ethics ; Heroin ; Internet ; Moral dilemmas ; Physiology ; Policy making ; Public health ; Social media ; Social networks
[115] Holger Pötzsch. Archives and identity in the context of social media and algorithmic analytics: Towards an understanding of iarchive and predictive retention. New media & society, 20(9):3304--3322, 2018.
This article reconceptualizes the archive in the context of digital media ecologies. Drawing upon archival theory and critical approaches to the political economy of the Internet, I account for new dynamics and implications afforded by digital archives. Operating at both a user-controlled explicit and a state- and corporate-owned implicit level, the digital archive at once facilitates empowerment and enables unprecedented forms of management and control. Connecting the politics and economy of digital media with issues of identity formation and curation on social networking sites, I coin the terms iArchive and predictive retention to highlight how recent technological advances both provide new means for self-expression, mobilization and resistance and afford an almost ubiquitous tracking, profiling and, indeed, moulding of emergent subjectivities.
[116] Rainer Forst. Noumenal power. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 23(2), 2015. [ DOI ]
[117] Claire Benn and Seth Lazar. What's wrong with automated influence. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 2021. [ DOI ]
Keywords: artificial intelligence; surveillance; privacy; exploitation; manipulation; legitimacy; power
[118] Andrew Roberts. Privacy in the republic. Routledge, 1 edition, 2023. [ DOI ]
[119] Belastingdienst/toeslagen, 2018.
[120] Philip Pettit. On the people's terms. Cambridge University Press, 2012.
Keywords: Political philosophy
[121] Mordecai Kurz. The market power of technology. Columbia University Press, 2023.
[122] Carissa Véliz. Privacy is power. Melville House Publishing, 2021.
Keywords: privacy; power; technology
[123] Steven Lukes. Power: a radical view. Palgrave Macmillan in assoc. with the British Sociological Association, Basingstoke, 2nd [exp.] edition, 2005.
Keywords: Power
[124] John Haugeland. Mind design II: philosophy, psychology, artificial intelligence. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass, rev. and enl. ed. edition, 1997.
Keywords: artificial intelligence ; cognitive psychology ; cognitive sciences/general ; philosophy/general
[125] Paul. Dourish and Genevieve. Bell. Divining a digital future : mess and mythology in ubiquitous computing. MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass, 2011.
Reflecting the interdisciplinary nature of the authors' collaboration, this book takes seriously the need to understand ubicomp not only technically but also culturally, socially politically and economically.
Keywords: Ubiquitous computing
[126] Noah Lemos. An introduction to the theory of knowledge. Cambridge University Press, 2 edition, 2021.
[127] John Oberdiek. Lost in moral space: On the infringing/violating distinction and its place in the theory of rights. Law and philosophy, 23(4):325--346, 2004.
Keywords: Abortion ; Analysis ; Beliefs, opinions and attitudes ; Debate ; Ethics ; Human rights ; Law ; Libertarianism ; Morality ; Normativity ; Philosophy ; Philosophy of law ; Private property ; Property damage ; Property ownership ; Property rights ; Rights ; Social aspects ; Tort law
[128] John Locke. Two treatises of government. Cambridge texts in the history of political thought. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge [etc, [rev. and abridged] student ed. / ed. with an introd. and notes by peter laslett. edition, 1988.
Keywords: Filmer, Robert, 1590-1653
[129] Ronald Myles Dworkin. Taking rights seriously. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1977.
Keywords: Law -- Philosophy
[130] HLA. Hart. Are there any natural rights? The Philosophical review, 64(2):175--191, 1955.
There is of course no simple identification to be made between moral and legal rights, but there is an intimate connection between the two, and this itself is one feature which distinguishes a moral right from other fundamental moral concepts. The words droit, diritto, and Recht, used by continental jurists, have no simple English translation and seem to English jurists to hover uncertainly between law and morals, but they do in fact mark off an area of morality which has special characteristics. In contrast with special rights, which constitute a justification peculiar to the holder of the right for interfering with another's freedom, are general rights, which are asserted defensively, when some unjustified interference is anticipated or threatened, in order to point out that the interference is unjustified. The assertion of general rights directly invokes the principle that all men equally have the right to be free; the assertion of a special right invokes it indirectly.
Keywords: Assertion ; Coercion ; Correlatives ; Equal rights ; Ethical codes ; Freedom of choice ; Fundamental rights ; Humans ; Intellectual freedom ; International human rights law ; Law and economics ; Morality ; Natural (music) ; Obedience ; Obligation ; Political science ; Promises ; Rights of Nature ; Simple (philosophy)
[131] Hillel Steiner. Directed duties and inalienable rights. Ethics, 123(2):230--244, 2013.
This essay advances and defends two claims: (a) that rights cannot be inalienable and (b) that even if they could be, this would not be morally justifiable.
Keywords: Analysis ; Correlatives ; Disabilities ; Disabled persons ; Employment ; Ethics ; Human rights ; Immunity ; Law ; Moral principles ; Morality ; Morals ; Natural rights ; Normativity ; Political science ; Rights ; Social justice ; Social norms ; Social theory ; Waivers ; Workdays
[132] Vittorio Bufacchi. The truth about rights. Journal of human rights, 7(4):311--326, 2008.
Arguably the biggest challenge facing theories of rights today comes from moral sceptics of all persuasions who are constantly singing the praises of anti-foundationalism, and in so-doing undermining the validity of human rights. This article has two principle aims: to show how different theories of rights tend to presuppose related theories of truth and to argue how Pragmatism, as a theory of truth and a theory of rights, can provide human rights with the foundations it desperately needs. Parts I and II will show how the two major schools of thought on the nature of rights, the Interest (or Benefit) Theory of Rights, and the Choice (or Will) Theory of Rights, correlate with two dominant theories of truth: the Correspondence and the Coherence Theory of Truth. Part III will explore the Pragmatist conception of truth and how it correlated with a Pragmatist Theory of Rights. Finally, Part IV will argue that in terms of human rights, the choice we face is not between foundationalism and anti-foundationalism. There is a third-way that deserves closer analysis called "quasi-foundationalism."
Keywords: Coherence theory of truth ; Conceptualization ; Epistemology ; Ethics ; Face (sociological concept) ; Foundationalism ; Fundamental rights ; Human Rights ; Law ; Morality ; Persuasion ; Philosophical thought ; Pragmatic theory of truth ; Pragmatism ; Schools ; Skepticism ; Social theory ; Sociology ; Truth
[133] Alan Gewirth. Are there any absolute rights? The Philosophical Quarterly (1950-), 31(122):1--16, 1981. [ http ]
[134] Istvan Hont. Jealousy of trade. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 2005.
Keywords: Competition, International -- History
[135] Matthew HKramer, Simmonds N.E., and Steiner Hillel. A Debate Over Rights: Philosophical Enquiries. Oxford University Press, 03 2000. [ DOI | http ]
This book engages in essay form in a lively debate over the fundamental characteristics of legal rights. Each chapter considers whether rights essentially protect individuals' interests --- as is contended by the Interest Theory of rights --- or whether they instead essentially enable individuals to make choices, as the Will Theory of rights maintains. The book addresses many questions, such as the following: What are the necessary and sufficient conditions for the existence of a legal right? What is the connection between the existence and the enforcement of a legal right (i.e., between legal rights and legal remedies)? Does the identification of legal rights inevitably involve ethical judgments? To what extent can rights be in conflict? The answers to these and related questions can illuminatingly clarify, though not finally resolve, some of the present-day controversies over abortion, euthanasia, and animal rights.
[136] Grégoire CN. Webber. Constituting rights by limitation, pages 116--146. Cambridge University Press, 2009. [ DOI ]
[137] SPressfield. The War of Art: Winning the Inner Creative Battle. Orion, 2003. [ http ]
[138] Joseph Campbell. De held met de duizend gezichten. Contact, 2 edition, 1990.
[139] John Mullarkey. Refractions of Reality: Philosophy and the Moving Image. Palgrave Macmillan, December 2008. [ DOI | http ]
[140] Tim Crane. Is there a perceptual relation?: 2006. In Aspects of Psychologism, pages 196--. Harvard University Press, 2014.
P. F. Strawson argued that `mature sensible experience (in general) presents itself as... animmediateconsciousness of the existence of things outside us' (1979: 97). He began his defence of this very natural idea by asking how someone might typically give a description of their current visual experience, and offered this example of such a description: `I see the red light of the setting sun filtering through the black and thickly clustered branches of the elms; I see the dappled deer grazing in groups on the vivid green grass ...' (1979: 97). In other words, in describing experience, we tend
Keywords: Argument from illusion ; Behavioral sciences ; Cognitive psychology ; Concept of mind ; Disjunctivism ; Hallucination ; Intentionalism ; Intentionality ; Mental objects ; Mental world ; Metaphysics ; Perception ; Perception theory ; Perceptual experiences ; Perceptual reality ; Philosophy ; Philosophy of mind ; Psychology ; Qualia ; Sensory perception ; Thought
[141] Jessica Brown. Semantic externalism and selfโ€knowledge. In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind. Oxford University Press, 01 2009. [ DOI ]
The distinctive claim made by semantic externalism is that a subject's thought contents are partly individuated by her environment, and do not supervene on her `inner states', such as her brain states. One of the main objections to this position is the claim that it is incompatible with self-knowledge. A subject's knowledge of her own thoughts seems quite different from her knowledge of what others think. A subject uses behavioural evidence to know what others think. However, typically, a subject can know what she herself thinks without inferring this from her own behaviour, and even prior to manifesting any behaviour which could constitute grounds for such an inference.
[142] Jan-Werner Mueller. Liberalism's forever crisis. https://www.project-syndicate.org/onpoint/opponents-and-defenders-of-political-liberalism-by-jan-werner-mueller-2024-01, 01 2024.
Across Western democracies, one finds many who casually dismiss liberalism as a self-justifying ideology for economicwinnersor colonialism. But with conservatives openly fantasizing about imposing their moral orthodoxy on the whole society, liberalism's critics should be careful what they wish for
[143] Laura Tyson and John Zysman. The new industrial policy and its critics. https://www.project-syndicate.org/onpoint/the-case-for-new-industrial-policy-by-laura-tyson-and-john-zysman-2023-11, 2023 11.
For many years, industrial policy was considered taboo in the United States and many other advanced economies, owing to assumptions that it is inherently protectionist and market-distorting. But context matters, and in today's world, state interventions to address market failures are exactly what is needed.
Keywords: industrial policy,united states,inflation,china,semiconductors,laura tyson,john zysman
[144] Hilary Putnam. The meaning of 'meaning'. In Philosophical Papers, Volume 2, volume 2. Cambridge University Press, 2011.
Keywords: Philosophy of language ; Social & political philosophy
[145] Lynne Rudder Baker. The reality of ordinary things, pages 25--48. Cambridge Studies in Philosophy. Cambridge University Press, 2007. [ DOI ]
[146] Olivier Assayas. Clouds of sils maria, 2014.
[147] S Coppola. Lost in translation, 2003.
[148] Lea Cantor. Zhuangzi on `happy fish' and the limits of human knowledge. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 28(2):216--230, 2020. [ DOI | arXiv | http ]
[149] Wenyu Xie. Approaching the dao: From lao zi to zhuang zi. Journal of Chinese philosophy, 27(4):469--488, 2000.
Keywords: 499-200 B.C. Warring States period ; China ; Chinese literature ; Chuang-tzu ; Dao de jing ; Historical studies (History of philosophy. History of ideas) ; Lao-tzu ; Laozi(ca. 570-ca. 490 B.C.) ; Literary works ; Non-western thinking ; Philosophers ; Philosophy ; Philosophy of religion ; prose ; Religious texts ; tao ; Taoism ; Writing ; Zhuangzi ; Zhuangzi(ca. 369-ca. 286 B.C.)
[150] Daniel Fried. What's in a dao?: Ontology and semiotics in laozi and zhuangzi. Dao : a journal of comparative philosophy, 11(4):419--436, 2012.
The present essay examines the conflicting ontological assumptions that one can find behind the word dao in the texts of the Laozi and Zhuangzi and argues that the relative indifference to these texts toward whether or not dao has an ontic reality should not be considered a flaw of early Daoism. Rather, the historical process by which the term dao collects various possible ontological implications can be thought of as a philosophical stance in its own right. That is, if the terms which one is obliged to use in discussing the immaterial necessarily hide, at least as much as they explain, the nature of Being, then it is a reasonable response to decline to ground one's ethics in an ontology, and that while the resulting philosophy may not qualify as a fully-adumbrated system, this does not diminish its potential usefulness.
Keywords: 499-200 B.C. Warring States period ; 799-500 B.C. Spring and Autumn period ; Arts & Humanities ; Asian Studies ; Chinese ; Chinese literature ; dao ; Dao de jing ; Education ; Essays ; Ethics ; Language ; Laozi(ca. 570-ca. 490 B.C.) ; Libraries ; Logic ; Non-Western Philosophy ; Ontology ; Philosophy ; Philosophy of Religion ; prose ; Realism ; Religious Studies ; Semiotics ; Taoism ; Zhuangzi ; Zhuangzi(ca. 369-ca. 286 B.C.)
[151] PJ. Invanhoe and Bryan W. van Norden. Readings in classical Chinese philosophy. second edition, 2005.
This new edition offers expanded selections from the works of Kongzi (Confucius), Mengzi (Mencius), Zhuangzi (Chuang Tzu), and Xunzi (Hsun Tzu); two new works, the dialogues Robber Zhi and White Horse ; a concise general introduction; brief introductions to, and selective bibliographies for, each work; and four appendices that shed light on important figures, periods, texts, and terms in Chinese thought.
Keywords: 08.10 non-western philosophy.; B126; B126 .R43 2005eb; Philosophy Chinese -- To 221 B.C; To 221 B.C
[152] Paul J. D'Ambrosio. Confucianism and daoism: On the relationship between the analects, laozi, and zhuangzi, part i. Philosophy Compass, 15(9):e12702, 2020. [ DOI | arXiv | http ]
Abstract The Lunyu ่ซ–่ชž (Analects of Confucius), Daodejing ้“ๅพท็ถ“ (Classic of the Way and Virtuosity) or Laozi ่€ๅญ (Book of Master Lao), and the Zhuangzi ่ŽŠๅญ (Book of Master Zhuang) have been broadly classified as representative of Confucianism (Lunyu) and Daoism (Laozi and Zhuangzi). This loose grouping, and the similarities and differences associated with theseschoolsinclude some of the most telling and simultaneously misleading generalizations about Chinese philosophy or thought in general. These articles seek to provide an overview of the relationship between Confucianism and Daoism. The first article begins before with a generalized topics based comparison of the Lunyu, Laozi and Zhuangzi. The latter two texts include their own significant differences, but I will, wherever possible, look for generalities that fit both. The major themes considered in this first part are (1) the perspectives on names (ming ๅ) and actualities (shi ๅฏฆ), (2) cultivation, learning, and what is considered natural (ziran ่‡ช็„ถ), and finally (3) conceptions of the person.
[153] Paul J. D'Ambrosio. Confucianism and daoism: On the relationship between the analects, laozi, and zhuangzi, part ii. Philosophy Compass, 15(9):e12701, 2020. [ DOI | arXiv | http ]
Abstract This article is a continuation of Part I, which looked at the relationship between Confucianism and Daoism by first introducing general approaches, before moving on to (1) perspectives on names and actualities; (2) cultivation, learning, the natural; and (3) conceptions of the person. Continuing with the theme-based comparison of Confucianism and Daoism by looking specifically at the Lunyu ่ซ–่ชž (Analects of Confucius), Daodejing ้“ๅพท็ถ“ (Classic of the Way and Virtuosity) or Laozi ่€ๅญ (Book of Master Lao), and the Zhuangzi ่ŽŠๅญ (Book of Master Zhuang), this article looks at (1) politics, nonaction (wuwei ็„ก็‚บ), and virtuosity (de ๅพท); (2) morality, virtues, and human nature (xing ๆ€ง); and finally (3) Dao ้“, orthe way.” It references Part I, and while it can be read independently, it is best taken as a continuation of Part I. The conclusion included herein summarizes both Part II and Part I.
[154] A.C. Graham. Disputers of the Tao: Philosophical Argument in Ancient China. Open Court, 2015. [ http ]
[155] A Hamilton. The mediascape of modern southeast asia. Screen, 33(1):81--92, 1992.
Keywords: Arts & Humanities ; dramatic arts ; Film Radio & Television ; Southeast Asia ; television ; videotape
[156] Gerald Sim. Postcolonial hangups in Southeast Asian cinema : poetics of space, sound, and stability. Critical Asian cinemas. Amsterdam University Press, 2020.
Postcolonial Hangups in Southeast Asian Cinema explores a geopolitically situated set of cultures negotiating unique relationships to colonial history. These particular Singaporean, Malaysian, and Indonesian identities are discussed through a variety of commercial films, art cinema, and experimental work. It discovers instances of postcoloniality that manifest stylistically through Singapore's preoccupations with space, the importance of sound to Malay culture, and the Indonesian investment in genre.
Keywords: PN1993.5.A755; PN1993.5.A755 .S56 2020; Motion pictures -- Southeast Asia -- History and criticism; Postcolonialism film theory Singapore Malaysia Indonesia
[157] Rick Altman. Film/genre. Bloomsbury Publishing, 1999.
Film/Genre revises our notions of film genre and connects the roles played by industry critics and audiences in making and re-making genre. Altman reveals the conflicting stakes for which the genre game has been played and recognises that the term 'genre' has different meanings for different groups, basing his new genre theory on the uneasy competitive yet complimentary relationship among genre users and discussing a huge range of films from The Great Train Robbery to Star Wars and from The Jazz Singer to The Player.
Keywords: PN1995; PN1995 .A383 1999; Film genres
[158] Benjamin Wormald. Religious composition by country, 2010-2050, Apr 2015. [ http ]
[159] Thomas Sobchack. Genre film: A classical experience. Literature/Film Quarterly, 3(3), Summer 1975. Last updated - 2013-02-23.
Keywords: Performing Arts
[160] Kathryn VanArendonk. Mike white accepts the criticism. https://www.vulture.com/article/the-white-lotus-finale-mike-white-interview-departures-ending.html, Aug 2021. [ .html ]
[161] John A. Lent. Southeast asian independent cinema: Independent of what? In Southeast Asian Independent Cinema, page 13. Hong Kong University Press, HKU, 2012.
To discuss Southeast Asian Independent Cinema is to encounter problems of definition, first, in trying to delineate the region itself, and second, in setting the parameters of independent film. Southeast Asia is a diverse mixture of many languages, cultures, and beliefs pulled together for political convenience; it is a colonial, and later, Cold War construct of Western origins. The region and in turn, its film, are not entities unto themselves; they are inseparable from their Indian, Malay, Chinese, and other roots. Similarly, a sole definition of independent cinema is not justified, with filmmakers and cinema scholars using the term in
Keywords: Anthropology ; Applied anthropology ; Applied sciences ; Arts ; Asian studies ; Behavioral sciences ; Business ; Business structures ; Censorship ; Communications ; Cultural anthropology ; Cultural customs ; Cultural industries ; Cultural studies ; Economic disciplines ; Economics ; Education ; Educational institutions ; Engineering ; Entertainment industries ; Ethnography ; Ethnology ; Film studies ; Finance ; Financial economics ; Formal education ; Funding ; Gasoline ; Holidays ; Industrial engineering ; Industrial refining ; Industrial sectors ; Industry ; Lent ; Manufacturing ; Manufacturing engineering ; Manufacturing processes ; Motion picture industry ; Movies ; Oil refining ; Petroleum distillates ; Petroleum products ; Political censorship ; Religious holidays ; Schools ; Social sciences ; South Asian studies ; Southeast Asian culture ; Southeast Asian studies ; Universities ; Visual arts
[162] Mark Alfino. Another look at the derrida-searle debate. Philosophy & rhetoric, 24(2):143--152, 1991.
A review of Limited Inc (Derrida, Jacques, Evanston, Ill: Northwestern U Press, 1988) collects some of the papers forming the Derrida-Searle debate of the 1970s. Although the debate was, & continues to be, hostile, important issues regarding speech act theory are raised. Derrida supports the original insight behind speech act theory but argues that it has been wrongly developed by John Austin & John Searle. Derrida argues that Austin is incorrect in characterizing communicative action as the determination of a context by a set of conventions & intentions. Derrida argues that a structure of absenceëxists in every meaningful use of language, & that language is characterized by ïterability.The views of Derrida & Searle on the relation between intention & iterability are contrasted, & some other issues raised by the debate are noted. 2 References. B. Annesser Murray
Keywords: Limited Inc abc... ; 1900-1999 ; Arts & Humanities ; Austin J. L ; Debate ; Deconstructionism ; Derrida Jacques ; Discussion Notes ; French literature ; How to Do Things with Words ; Intentionality ; Language ; Literary theory ; Literature ; Phenomena ; Philosophy ; pragmatics ; Presuppositions ; prose ; review article ; Searle John R ; Speech act theory ; Speech acts ; Words
[163] Raoul Moati, Timothy Attanucci, and Maureen Chun. Derrida, Searle: deconstruction and ordinary language. Columbia university Press, New York, 2014.
Raoul Moati intervenes in the critical debate that divided two prominent philosophers in the mid-twentieth century. In the 1950s, the British philosopher J. L. Austin advanced a theory of speech acts, or the performative,that Jacques Derrida and John R. Searle interpreted in fundamentally different ways. Their disagreement centered on the issue of intentionality, which Derrida understood phenomenologically and Searle read pragmatically. The controversy had profound implications for the development of contemporary philosophy, which, Moati argues, can profit greatly by returning to this classic debate. In this book, Moati systematically replays the historical encounter between Austin, Derrida, and Searle and the disruption that caused the lasting break between Anglo-American language philosophy and continental traditions of phenomenology and its deconstruction. The key issue, Moati argues, is not whether ïntentionalityconcept derived from Husserl's phenomenology, can or cannot be linked to Austin's speech-acts as defined in his groundbreaking How to Do Things with Words, but rather the emphasis Searle placed on the performativity and determined pragmatic values of Austin's speech-acts, whereas Derrida insisted on the trace of writing behind every act of speech and the iterability of signs in different contexts.
Keywords: 20th century ; Deconstruction ; Derrida Jacques ; Intentionality (Philosophy) ; Language and languages ; Ordinary-language philosophy ; Performative (Philosophy) ; Philosophy ; Searle John R ; Speech acts (Linguistics)
[164] R Hull. Styling nietzsche - a note on the genealogy of derridean deconstruction. Man and World, 27(3):325--333, 1994.
Keywords: Arts & Humanities ; Philosophical logics. Philosophy of language ; Philosophy
[165] JL. (John Langshaw) Austin. How to do things with words. The William James lectures How to do things with words. Clarendon, Oxford, second edition, 1975.
This work sets out Austin's conclusions in the field to which he directed his main efforts for at least the last ten years of his life. Starting from an exhaustive examination of his already well-known distinction between performative utterances and statements, Austin here finally abandons that distinction, replacing it with a more general theory of 'illocutionary forces' of utterances which has important bearings on a wide variety of philosophical problems.
Keywords: P106.A9 1975; Language and languages -- Philosophy; Speech acts (Linguistics)
[166] Peter Bornedal. Deconstructive vs pragmatic: A critique of the derrida-searle debate. The European legacy, toward new paradigms, 25(1):62--81, 2020.
This article presents a critical account of the debate between Derrida and Searle in which I defend Austin's and Searle's pragmatic analysis of speech against Derrida's complex deconstructionist approach. I first formalize Derrida's argument, reducing it to its main tenets that can be positively identified and critically reviewed. On the basis of this formalization I argue that the apparent incompatibility between Derrida's and Searle's approach to language becomes clear once we formalize, according to their type and content, the three concepts of ïntentionthat are confusedly referred to under one and the same label in the debate. This formalization reduces and clarifies the obscurity associated with the Derrida-Searle debate, and helps demonstrating the shortcomings of Derrida's position.
Keywords: Austin ; Deconstruction ; Derrida ; Derrida Jacques ; Intention ; Pragmatism ; Searle ; Speech ; Speech-Act theory
[167] Theodor Adorno. Critical models : interventions and catchwords. European perspectives 850132967. Columbia University Press, New York, [NY etc.], [new ed.] edition, 2005.
Keywords: 08.25 contemporary western philosophy (20th and 21th century); HN16
[168] Max Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno. Dialectiek van de verlichting. Boom, Amsterdam, fourth edition, 2022.
Keywords: Philosophy of culture.; 08.42 philosophy of culture.
[169] José Ortega y Gasset. De opstand van de massamens. Lemniscaat, Rotterdam, second edition, 2015.
[170] Peter Sloterdijk. De verschrikkelijke kinderen van de nieuwe tijd. Boom, Amsterdam, 2014.
[171] Harry Frankfurt. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. The Journal of philosophy, 68(1), 1971.
Keywords: Addiction ; Analytic Philosophy ; Animals ; Contemporary Philosophy ; Desire ; Free will ; Humans ; Legal entities ; Moral responsibility ; Rationality ; Verbs ; Volition
[172] Robert Kane. Responsibility, luck, and chance: Reflections on free will and indeterminism. The Journal of philosophy, 96(5), 1999.
The problem of free will and determinism is discussed, with a focus on defending libertarian freedom without appeal to extracausal factors. Topics include the luck principle, indeterminism, the relationship between indeterminism and responsibility, possible worlds and the luck principle, parallel processing, control and explanation.
Keywords: Accidents ; Arts & Humanities ; Assassinations ; Beliefs opinions and attitudes ; Businesspeople ; Chance ; Dennett Daniel C ; Determinism ; Free will ; Free will and determinism ; Freedom of choice ; Incompatibilism ; Indeterminism ; Modal realism ; Philosophy ; Philosophy of action ; Responsibility ; Temptation ; Theory of values and moral philosophy. Philosophy of action
[173] Harry Frankfurt. Identification and wholeheartedness. In Perspectives on Moral Responsibility. Cornell University Press, 2018.
The phrasethe mind-body problemis so crisp, and its role in philosophical discourse is so well established, that to oppose its use would simply be foolish. Nonetheless, the usageisrather anachronistic. The familiar problem to which the phrase refers concerns the relationship between a creature's body and the fact that the creature is conscious. A more appropriate name would be, accordingly, “the consciousness--body problem.” For it is no longer plausible to equate the realm of conscious phenomena---as Descartes did---with the realm of mind. This is not only because psychoanalysis has made the notion of unconscious
[174] Ryan Philip Gardener. Screaming silently : Haan, contemporary south korean cinema, and emotional realism, 2020.
Through this thesis I examine how popular contemporary South Korean cinema addresses, appeals to, and is shaped by Korea's social, historical, and cultural context, specifically by drawing on the cultural concept of haan - a national sentiment that draws on notions of accumulated suffering and resentment in the Korean context. Rather than viewing haan as an essential component of South Korean cinema - as has often been the critical tendency - I seek to understand the function of haan within that cinema. My first chapter establishes a framework for examining haan, by understanding cinematic evocation of haan in relation to emotional realism - a mode of address that communicates the emotion of reality, if not its factual or aesthetic reality. Seen in respect to emotional realism, I argue, haan communicates Korean social and historical realism through emotional address. My second chapter charts Korean cinema's portrayal of the 1980 Gwangju Democratic Uprising and argues how, despite the film-to-film differences in representation, haan is a constant in how Korean cinema emotionally frames the events of Gwangju, and thus mediates them within South Korean cultural memory. My third chapter focuses on a recent wave of films set during Korea's 1910 to 1945 colonisation by Japan, drawing on consistencies in how haan is evoked during these films' thematic elaboration of various issues relating to national identity. My fourth chapter, focusses on how haan manifests in South Korea's blockbuster cinema, arguing that haan is frequently structured into cinematic spectacle, often through the creation of emotional spectacle. Through this structure, and predominantly through textual analysis, my thesis discusses how haan's cinematic evocation appeals to the national by drawing on sentiments of deep cultural resonance within the Korean context. Such appeal, when afforded precedence in the textual assemblage of a film, I argue, is of great significance to some of South Korean cinema's most culturally important and domestically successful films.
Keywords: Cultural heritage ; Realism
[175] Anthony Carew. Quiet rage. Metro (Melbourne), (200):86--93, 2019.
In Burning, we hear a presidential speech playing on the television owned by Jong-su (Yoo Ah-in), an aspiring writer who's been forced - by his father's legal troubles - to return to his downtrodden hometown and work the family farm. While he has particular filmmaking fondnesses - meting out classic melodrama over slow-moving works of realism, karaoke, incongruously jaunty music, rivers and trains as symbolic images of the movement of time, characters riding in cars and on buses, depictions of people with disabilities - Lee is still a novelist at heart, his micro stories suggesting macro ideas. Peppermint Candy is an even more explicit study of an evolving Korea: set at various points throughout recent history, its story mirrors the politico-economic cycles of the nation itself. Describing train travel as having altered 'mankind's perception of time', he went on to say: 'Film is, of course, a medium that deals with time, and in that sense, the fact that one of the first films ever made is [the Lumiere Brothers'] Arrival of a Train [1896] is very symbolic.'14 Peppermint Candy opens in Spring 1999 with a sad, drunk salaryman, Yong-ho (Sol Kyung-gu), stumbling along a rubbish-strewn riverbank; there, a party of people have gathered to sing karaoke.
[176] Michael C Reiff. Burning. Film & History, 49(2):54--57, 2019.
Lee Chang-dong's film is reviewed.
Keywords: Burning (Motion picture : 2018) ; Criticism and interpretation ; Drama ; Lee Chang-Dong (Yi Chang-dong) (1954- ) ; Man-woman relationships ; Motion picture directors & producers ; Motion pictures ; Movie reviews ; Murakami Haruki (1949- ) ; Murders & murder attempts ; Mysteries ; Violence ; Yi Ch'ang-dong
[177] Björn Boman. The multifold intertextuality in lee chang dong's burning. Social sciences & humanities open, 3(1):100--119, 2021.
The study focuses on how the South Korean drama/mystery film Burning (2018) intertextually draws from William Faulkner's short story `Barn burning' and Haruki Murakami's short story `Barn burning' and related sociohistorical contexts. Burning does quite impressionistically and freely draw from these two short stories as well as adding new features, while simultaneously removing much of the core of Faulkner's work and some of Murakami's counterpart. By means of intertextual borrowing and re-contextualization, it has used the global discursive field and consequently hybridized and localized elements and themes from American-Western and Japanese works and discourses to perhaps make them better suited for the South Korean context. Burning has included and excluded various elements from both short stories but emphasized class and gender issues. These two major elements reflect upon the structural inequalities in the contemporary South Korean society.
Keywords: Burning ; General Literature Studies ; Haruki Murakami ; Humaniora och konst ; Humanities and the Arts ; Intertextuality ; Languages and Literature ; Litteraturvetenskap ; South Korea ; Språk och litteratur ; William Faulkner
[178] Steve Choe. Sovereign violence : ethics and South Korean cinema in the new millennium. Film culture in transition. Amsterdam University Press, 2016.
South Korea is home to one of the most vibrant film industries in the world today, producing movies for a strong domestic market that are also drawing the attention of audiences worldwide. This book presents a comprehensive analysis of some of the most well-known and incendiary South Korean films of the millennial decade from nine major directors. Building his analysis on contemporary film theory and philosophy, as well as interviews and other primary sources, Steve Choe makes a case that these often violent films pose urgent ethical dilemmas central to life in the age of neoliberal globalization.
Keywords: PN1993.5.K6; PN1993.5.K6 C484 2016; Motion pictures -- Social aspects -- Korea (South); Violence in motion pictures
[179] John Marenbon. Medieval philosophy. Routledge, 2007.
[180] John McGinnis and David C. Reisman. Classical Arabic philosophy : an anthology of sources. Hackett Pub. Co., Indianapolis, 2007.
This volume introduces the major classical Arabic philosophers through substantial selections from the key works (many of which appear in translation for the first time here) in each of the fields--including logic, philosophy of science, natural philosophy, metaphysics, ethics, and politics--to which they made significant contributions.
Keywords: B741; B741 .C52 2007; Islamic philosophy; Geschichte
[181] Muhammad b. Muhammad al Ġazali. The incoherence of the philosophers = Tahafut al-falasifa : a parallel English-Arabic text. Islamic translation series 197020224. Brigham Young University Press, Provo, Utah, second edition, 2000.
Keywords: 08.22 medieval philosophy.; Didactical prose (texts); B753.G33; B753.G33 T3313 2000; Philosophy -- Early works to 1800; Methodology -- Early works to 1800; Faith and reason -- Early works to 1800 -- Islam; Islam -- Doctrines; Islam -- Doctrines -- Ouvrages avant 1800
[182] Edward S. Herman and Noam Chomsky. Manufacturing Consent. Pantheon Books, 2 edition, 2002.
[183] Daniel H. Frank and Oliver Leaman, editors. History of Jewish philosophy. Routledge history of world philosophies ; v. 2. Routledge, London ; New York, 1997.
Jewish philosophy is often presented as an addendum to Jewish religion rather than as a rich and varied tradition in its own right, but the History of Jewish Philosophy explores the entire scope and variety of Jewish philosophy from philosophical interpretations of the Bible right up to contemporary Jewish feminist and postmodernist thought. The links between Jewish philosophy and its wider cultural context are stressed, building up a comprehensive and historically sensitive view of Jewish philosophy and its place in the development of philosophy as a whole. Includes:ยท Det
Keywords: B154; B154 .H57 1997; Jewish philosophy -- History; Judaism -- History
[184] HL. A. (Herbert Lionel Adolphus) Hart. The concept of law. Clarendon law series. Oxford University Press, third edition, 2012.
Fifty years on from its original publication, HLA Hart's The Concept of Law is widely recognized as the most important work of legal philosophy published in the twentieth century. It is a classic book in the field of legal scholarship and remains the starting point for most students coming to the subject for the first time. Known as Hart's most famous work, The Concept of Law emerged from a set of lectures that Hart began to deliver in 1952 in which he developed a sophisticated view of legal positivism. Hart revolutionized the methods of jurisprudence and the philosophy of law in the English-speaking world by bringing the tools of analytic, and especially linguistic, philosophy to bear on the central problems of legal theory. In this third edition, Leslie Green provides a new introduction that sets the book in the context of subsequent developments in social and political philosophy, clarifying misunderstandings of Hart's project and highlighting central tensions and problems in the work. The Concept of Law remains a must-read for anyone interested in the great thinkers of the 20th century.
Keywords: 86.04 philosophy of law.; K237; K237 .H3 2012eb; Jurisprudence -- Methodology; Law -- Philosophy
[185] Fazlur Rahman. Islamic methodology in history. Publications of the Central Institute of Islamic Research, Pakistan ; publ. no. 2 117027499. Central inst. of Islamic research, Karachi, 1965.
Keywords: Islam.; Theology.; Methodology.; 11.80 Islam: general.; History (form); KBP440.3; KBP440.3 .R34 1965; Islam
[186] Masooda Bano. The Revival of Islamic Rationalism: Logic, Metaphysics and Mysticism in Modern Muslim Societies. Cambridge University Press, 2020. [ DOI ]
[187] George Boas. Rationalism in Greek Philosophy. Johns Hopkins University Press, 2019.
Originally published in 1961. Greek philosophers were concerned with the distinction between appearance and reality, and all the differences in their philosophic systems were ultimately predicated on their different views of this distinction. The history of Greek rationalism is, then, a study of the changing basis of Greek philosophy. George Boas provides a historical account of rationalism in classical philosophy. He focuses on four central topics: the distinction between appearance and reality, the method used to establish the distinction, the appraisal of life made by the philosophers studied, and their ethical theories.
Keywords: Ancient philosophy ; bic Book Industry Communication ; H Humanities ; HP Philosophy ; HPC History of Western philosophy ; HPCA Western philosophy: Ancient ; to c 500
[188] Richard Taylor. Ibn rushd/averroes and ïslamicrationalism. Medieval encounters : Jewish, Christian, and Muslim culture in confluence and dialogue, 15(2-4):225--235, 2009.
Keywords: 400-1499 Medieval period ; Arabic language literature ; Aristotle(384-322 B.C.) ; Christian theology ; CREATION ; DEMONSTRATION ; DOUBLE TRUTH ; Fasl al-maqal ; GOD ; Ibn Rushd ; METAPHYSICS ; PHILOSOPHERS ; prose ; RATIONALISM ; REASON ; REFLECTION ; RELIGION ; RENAISSANCE ; Spanish literature ; Tafsir ma ba'd al-tabi'ah ; THEOLOGIANS
[189] Robert Kane. The significance of free will. Oxford University Press, New York ; Oxford, 1998.
Kane offers a provocative and original account of the issues surrounding free will and moral responsibility. He presents a version of the 'incompatibilist' or 'libertarian' view of free will, defending the classic view of free will as 'the power of agents to be the ultimate creators and sustainers of their own ends and purposes'.
Keywords: BJ1461; BJ1461 .K38 1998; Free will and determinism; Responsibility
[190] Karim Townsend. On mike white's primitivist posthumanisms: Animality, coloniality, and racial affect in the white lotus. Quarterly review of film and video, ahead-of-print(ahead-of-print), 2023.
[191] Kathryn Reklis. The ultrarich and their total depravity. The Christian century (1902), 138(26), 2021.
By choosing a small, Hawaiian island, he can probe the longer colonial histories tangled up in this racialized division of labor: local dancers perform än authentic indigenous dancefor the guests over dinner, the resort is built on land acquired unfairly from local residents, and it has so decimated the local economy that Lani feels grateful to work through her contractions. Kathryn Reklis teaches theology at Fordham University The camera repeatedly pans out to show us the expansive ocean and mountain ranges that surround the hotel, a wild luxury of beauty. [...]after six episodes, it was a necessary reminder that there are alternative visions of human life, in which purpose and power are not tied to wealth, even if it is harder for a camel to pass through the eye of a needle than for a rich man to find such a vision.
Keywords: Pain ; Television program reviews ; Television programs ; Wealth
[192] Judy Berman. Vacation, all they never wanted. Time, 198(3/4), 2021.
Berman reviews the television show, The White Lotus, on HBO.
Keywords: Television programs
[193] Jack Halberstam. Gender trouble in paradise. Representations (Berkeley, Calif.), 158(1), 2022.
IN A 2021 HBO SERIES, The two teenagers, Olivia (played by Sydney Sweeney) and Paula (Brittany O'Grady), spend huge amounts of time sitting casually by a large swimming pool not sunning simply but (gasp!) reading. Their choice of scholarly material clearly comments on the themes of the show. Judith Butler's classic book Gender Trouble makes a quick and unheralded appearance. Gender Trouble shows up when Paula pulls it out of her bag while rooting around for her medication. Butler is more famous than Susan Sontag, more ethical and generous than Jacques Derrida, and more likeable and funnier than Slavoj Zizek. Butler is, in short, a superstar, a phallic authority, a celebrity. And as such, their books can be thrown into the crockpot of an HBO show angling for intellectual credibility and can signify accordingly! What does Gender Trouble signify in The White Lotus? Not much in relation to the cringe-worthy plot of wealthy do-nothings taking time away from their busy lives of leisure to lie in the sun, receive massages from native people, and congratulate themselves on living well. But the book means a lot within the intertextual web established by the visual tagging of the teens' readerly aspirations. There, in conversation with Césaire and Fanon in particular, and operating at the level of the show's unconscious (as referenced by Freud and Lacan), Gender Trouble is a little bomb landing in the middle of the family romance of colonial occupation, lighting up the violent entanglements of intimacy, the natural, the exotic, and the financial and troubling all of them. Gender Trouble in The White Lotus is not a simple feminist refusal of the roles assigned to men and women across the genre of vacations gone wrong; rather, the book indexes other forms of instability that lurk beneath the surface of all luxury tourism where white violence has cleared the way for white relaxation.
Keywords: Butler Judith ; Gender studies ; Philosophy ; Television programs ; Tourism ; Violence ; White people
[194] Hannah Arendt. Freedom and politics: a lecture. Chicago review, 14(1), 1960.
Keywords: Ancient philosophy ; English Literature ; ESSAYS ; Freedom ; Freedom of speech ; Freedom to read ; General Literary Studies ; Intellectual freedom ; Political freedom ; Political ideologies ; Political philosophy ; Religious freedom ; Social contract
[195] FA Hayek. Freedom and coercion. In Liberty Reader. Routledge, United States, first edition, 2006.
In the sense 'freedom' refers solely to a relation of men to other men, and the only infringement on it is coercion by men. Freedom presupposes that the individual has some assured private sphere, that there is some set of circumstances in his environment with which others cannot interfere. The transition from the concept of individual liberty to that of liberty as power has been facilitated by the philosophical tradition that uses the word 'restraint' where reader have used 'coercion' in defining liberty. Coercion occurs when one man's actions are made to serve another man's will, not for his own but for the other's purpose. The freedom of the free may have differed widely, but only in the degree of an independence which the slave did not possess at all. The conception of liberty can be made more precise only after people have examined the related concept of coercion.
Keywords: PHILOSOPHY ; Sociology
[196] Shoshana Zuboff. The age of surveillance capitalism : the fight for a human future at the new frontier of power. Profile Books Ltd, first edition, 2019.
Shoshana Zuboff, named the true prophet of the information ageby the Financial Times, has always been ahead of her time. Her seminal book In the Age of the Smart Machine foresaw the consequences of a then-unfolding era of computer technology. Now, three decades later she asks why the once-celebrated miracle of digital is turning into a nightmare. Zuboff tackles the social, political, business, personal, and technological meaning of surveillance capitalismäs an unprecedented new market form. It is not simply about tracking us and selling ads, it is the business model for an ominous new marketplace that aims at nothing less than predicting and modifying our everyday behavior--where we go, what we do, what we say, how we feel, who we're with. The consequences of surveillance capitalism for us as individuals and as a society vividly come to life in The Age of Surveillance Capitalism's pathbreaking analysis of power. The threat has shifted from a totalitarian big brotherstate to a universal global architecture of automatic sensors and smart capabilities: A big otherthat imposes a fundamentally new form of power and unprecedented concentrations of knowledge in private companies--free from democratic oversight and control
Keywords: 05.20 communication and society.; Consumer behavior; Information technology; HF5415.32; HF5415.32 .Z83 2019 -- Data processing; Consumer profiling -- Data processing -- Social aspects; Nonfiction
[197] Phillip W. Magness and Michael Makovi. The mainstreaming of marx: Measuring the effect of the russian revolution on karl marx's influence. Journal of political economy, 131(6):1507--1545, 2023. [ DOI | arXiv | http ]
Karl Marx's high academic stature outside of economics diverges sharply from his peripheral influence within the discipline, particularly after nineteenth-century developments rendered the labor theory of value obsolete. We hypothesize that the 1917 Russian Revolution is responsible for elevating Marx into the academic mainstream. Using the synthetic control method, we construct a counterfactual for Marx's citation patterns in Google Ngram data. This allows us to predict how often Marx would have been cited if the Russian Revolution had not happened. We find a significant treatment effect, meaning that Marx's academic stature today owes a substantial debt to political happenstance.
[198] Jan-Maarten van Sonsbeek, Frits Bos, Jos Ebregt, and Eugene Verkade. De nederlandse economie in historisch perspectief, 2023. [ arXiv | http ]
Deze historische analyse laat de ontwikkeling van de Nederlandse economie zien in een handzaam overzicht van kerncijfers, trends en verklarende factoren. Dit helpt te begrijpen waarom Nederland het land is geworden dat het nu is, hoe we ons huidige welvaartsniveau bereikt hebben, welke factoren daaraan ten grondslag liggen, maar ook wat dat ons gekost heeft.
[199] Michel Korzec. De kitsch van het holisme. Veen, 1986.
Een twistschrift over de eenheid van het verhevene, het ware, het goede, het schone en de toepassing derzelve op het wezenlijke in mensch, maatschappij en het heel-al inzonderheid de zeer aanmerkelijke ontaarding daarvan bij Capra en daarvan afgetrokken verhandelingen over wiskonstige en andere wetenschappen alsmede onderrichtingen over dood en eeuwigheid profluerend uit de drukking des dampkrings, de oerstraling, de aantrekkingskracht, de magnetische, elektromagnetische en andere verschijnselen die in hun uitgestrektheid alle zouden wijzen op de ijdelheid van alle huidige konsten en wetenschappen daarnevens de toename van algemeen kwaad, rampspoed en besmettelijke ziekten tutti quanti aantonend de onontkoombaarheid van de herschepping van de Aarde in haar oorspronkelijke Natuur inachtnemend de Wijsheid der Oude Chineezen en met dat al een trouwhartige waarschuwing behelzend tegen dit uit 's wereldsonstandvastigheid voortkomend gemoed en het aanprijzen derzulken als een filosofie en liefdesethos voor vrouwen.
[200] Rabindranath Tagore. De koning van de donkere kamer. Wereldbibliotheek, 1971.
[201] Etty Hillesum and J.G. Gaarlandt. Het verstoorde leven. Uitgeverij Balans, forty-first edition, 2022.
[202] Carl G Hempel. The logical analysis of psychology. In Selected philosophical essays, pages 165--180. 2000.
One of the most important and most discussed problems of contemporary philosophy is that of determining how psychology should be characterized in the theory of science. This problem, overflowing the limits of epistemological analysis and leading to heated controversy in metaphysics itself, is brought to a focus by this familiar disjunction: “Is psychology a natural science, or is it one of the sciences of mind and culture (Geisteswissenchaften)?”The present article attempts to sketch the general lines of a new analysis of psychology, one which makes use of rigorous logical tools and which has made possible decisive advances toward the solution of the above problem. This analysis was successfully undertaken by the Vienna Circle (Wiener Kreis), the members of which (M. Schlick, R. Carnap, Phillipp Frank, o. Neurath, F. Waismann, H. Feigl, etc.) have, during the past ten years, developed an extremely fruitful method for the epistemological examination and critique of the various sciences, based in part on the work of L. Wittgenstein. We shall limit ourselves essentially to the examination of psychology as carried out by Carnap and Neurath.The method characteristic of the studies of the Vienna Circle can be briefly defined as a logical analysis of the language of science. This method became possible only with the development of an extremely subtle logical apparatus which makes use, in particular, of all the formal procedures of modern logistics.
[203] Gerardus en Novalis van der Leeuw. Uren met Novalis. second edition, 1943.

This file was generated by bibtex2html 1.99.